ROUSSEAU
Introduction
Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, the least academic of modern philosophers, was in many ways the
most influential. His thought marked the end of the Age of Reason and the
birth of Romanticism. He propelled political and ethical thinking into
new channels. His reforms revolutionized taste, first in music, then in
the other arts. He had a profound impact on people's way of life; he taught
parents to take a new interest in their children and to educate them differently;
he furthered the expression of emotion rather than polite restraint in
friendship and love. He introduced the cult of religious sentiment among
people who had discarded religious dogma. He opened men's eyes to the beauties
of nature, and he made liberty an object of almost universal aspiration.
Formative
years
Rousseau
was born in Geneva--the city of Calvin--on June 28, 1712. His mother died
in childbirth and he was brought up by his father, who taught him to believe
that the city of his birth was a republic as splendid as Sparta or ancient
Rome. Rousseau senior had an equally glorious image of his own importance;
after marrying above his modest station as a watchmaker, he got into trouble
with the civil authorities by brandishing the sword that his upper-class
pretentions prompted him to wear, and he had to leave Geneva to avoid imprisonment.
Rousseau, the son, then lived for six years as a poor relation in his mother's
family, patronized and humiliated, until he, too, at the age of 16, fled
from Geneva to live the life of an adventurer and a Roman Catholic convert
in the kingdoms of Sardinia and France.
Rousseau
was fortunate in finding in the province of Savoy a benefactress named
the Baronne de Warens, who provided him with a refuge in her home and employed
him as her steward. She also furthered his education to such a degree that
the boy who had arrived on her doorstep as a stammering apprentice who
had never been to school developed into a philosopher, a man of letters,
and a musician.
Mme
de Warens, who thus transformed the adventurer into a philosopher, was
herself an adventuress--a Swiss convert to Catholicism who had stripped
her husband of his money before fleeing to Savoy with the gardener's son
to set herself up as a Catholic missionary specializing in the conversion
of young male Protestants. Her morals distressed Rousseau, even when he
became her lover. But she was a woman of taste, intelligence, and energy,
who brought out in Rousseau just the talents that were needed to conquer
Paris at a time when Voltaire had made radical ideas fashionable.
Rousseau
reached Paris when he was 30 and was lucky enough to meet another young
man from the provinces seeking literary fame in the capital, Denis Diderot.
The two soon became immensely successful as the centre of a group of intellectuals--or
"Philosophes"--who gathered round the great French Encyclopédie,
of which Diderot was appointed editor. The Encyclopédie was an important
organ of radical and anticlerical opinion, and its contributors were as
much reforming and even iconoclastic pamphleteers as they were philosophers.
Rousseau, the most original of them all in his thinking and the most forceful
and eloquent in his style of writing, was soon the most conspicuous. He
wrote music as well as prose, and one of his operas, Le Devin du village
(1752; The Cunning-Man), attracted so much admiration from the king and
the court that he might have enjoyed an easy life as a fashionable composer,
but something in his Calvinist blood rejected this type of worldly glory.
Indeed, at the age of 37 Rousseau had what he called an "illumination"
while walking to Vincennes to visit Diderot, who had been imprisoned there
because of his irreligious writings. In the Confessions, which he wrote
late in life, Rousseau says that it came to him then in a "terrible flash"
that modern progress had corrupted instead of improved men. He went on
to write his first important work, a prize essay for the Academy of Dijon
entitled Discours sur les sciences et les arts (1750; A Discourse on the
Sciences and the Arts), in which he argues that the history of man's life
on earth has been a history of decay.
This
Discourse is by no means Rousseau's best piece of writing, but its central
theme was to inform almost everything else he wrote. Throughout his life
he kept returning to the thought that man is good by nature but has been
corrupted by society and civilization. He did not mean to suggest that
society and civilization were inherently bad but rather that both had taken
a wrong direction and become more harmful as they had become more sophisticated.
This idea in itself was not unfamiliar when Rousseau published his Discourse
on the Sciences and the Arts. Many Roman Catholic writers deplored the
direction that European culture had taken since the Middle Ages. They shared
the hostility toward progress that Rousseau had expressed. What they did
not share was his belief that man was naturally good. It was, however,
just this belief in man's natural goodness that Rousseau made the cornerstone
of his argument.
Rousseau
may well have received the inspiration for this belief from Mme de Warens;
for although that unusual woman had become a communicant of the Roman Catholic
Church, she retained--and transmitted to Rousseau--much of the sentimental
optimism about human purity that she had herself absorbed as a child from
the mystical Protestant Pietists who were her teachers in the canton of
Bern. At all events, the idea of man's natural goodness, as Rousseau developed
it, set him apart from both conservatives and radicals. Even so, for several
years after the publication of his first Discourse, he remained a close
collaborator in Diderot's essentially progressive enterprise, the Encyclopédie,
and an active contributor to its pages. His speciality there was music,
and it was in this sphere that he first established his influence as reformer.
Controversy
with Rameau.
The
arrival of an Italian opera company in Paris in 1752 to perform works of
opera buffa by Pergolesi, Scarlatti, Vinci, Leo, and other such composers
suddenly divided the French music-loving public into two excited camps,
supporters of the new Italian opera and supporters of the traditional French
opera. The Philosophes of the Encyclopédie--d'Alembert, Diderot,
and d'Holbach among them--entered the fray as champions of Italian music,
but Rousseau, who had arranged for the publication of Pergolesi's music
in Paris and who knew more about the subject than most Frenchmen after
the months he had spent visiting the opera houses of Venice during his
time as secretary to the French ambassador to the doge in 1743-44, emerged
as the most forceful and effective combatant. He was the only one to direct
his fire squarely at the leading living exponent of French operatic music,
Jean-Philippe Rameau.
Rousseau
and Rameau must at that time have seemed unevenly matched in a controversy
about music. Rameau, already in his 70th year, was not only a prolific
and successful composer but was also, as the author of the celebrated Traité
de l'harmonie (1722; Treatise on Harmony) and other technical works, Europe's
leading musicologist. Rousseau, by contrast, was 30 years younger, a newcomer
to music, with no professional training and only one successful opera to
his credit. His scheme for a new notation for music had been rejected by
the Academy of Sciences, and most of his musical entries for Diderot's
Encyclopédie were as yet unpublished. Yet the dispute was not only
musical but also philosophical, and Rameau was confronted with a more formidable
adversary than he had realized. Rousseau built his case for the superiority
of Italian music over French on the principle that melody must have priority
over harmony, whereas Rameau based his on the assertion that harmony must
have priority over melody. By pleading for melody, Rousseau introduced
what later came to be recognized as a characteristic idea of Romanticism,
namely, that in art the free expression of the creative spirit is more
important than strict adhesion to formal rules and traditional procedures.
By pleading for harmony, Rameau reaffirmed the first principle of French
Classicism, namely, that conformity to rationally intelligible rules is
a necessary condition of art, the aim of which is to impose order on the
chaos of human experience.
In
music, Rousseau was a liberator. He argued for freedom in music, and he
pointed to the Italian composers as models to be followed. In doing so
he had more success than Rameau; he changed people's attitudes. Gluck,
who succeeded Rameau as the most important operatic composer in France,
acknowledged his debt to Rousseau's teaching, and Mozart based the text
for his one-act operetta Bastien und Bastienne on Rousseau's Devin du village.
European music had taken a new direction. But Rousseau himself composed
no more operas. Despite the success of Le Devin du village, or rather because
of its success, Rousseau felt that, as a moralist who had decided to make
a break with worldly values, he could not allow himself to go on working
for the theatre. He decided to devote his energies henceforth to literature
and philosophy.
Major
works of political philosophy.
As
part of what Rousseau called his "reform," or improvement of his own character,
he began to look back at some of the austere principles that he had learned
as a child in the Calvinist republic of Geneva. Indeed he decided to return
to that city, repudiate his Catholicism, and seek readmission to the Protestant
church. He had in the meantime acquired a mistress, an illiterate laundry
maid named Thérèse Levasseur. To the surprise of his friends,
he took her with him to Geneva, presenting her as a nurse. Although her
presence caused some murmurings, Rousseau was readmitted easily to the
Calvinist communion, his literary fame having made him very welcome to
a city that prided itself as much on its culture as on its morals.
Rousseau
had by this time completed a second Discourse in response to a question
set by the Academy of Dijon: "What is the origin of the inequality among
men and is it justified by natural law?" In response to this challenge
he produced a masterpiece of speculative anthropology. The argument follows
on that of his first Discourse by developing the proposition that natural
man is good and then tracing the successive stages by which man has descended
from primitive innocence to corrupt sophistication.
Rousseau
begins his Discours sur l'origine de l'inegalité (1755; Discourse
on the Origin of Inequality) by distinguishing two kinds of inequality,
natural and artificial, the first arising from differences in strength,
intelligence, and so forth, the second from the conventions that govern
societies. It is the inequalities of the latter sort that he sets out to
explain. Adopting what he thought the properly "scientific" method of investigating
origins, he attempts to reconstruct the earliest phases of man's experience
of life on earth. He suggests that original man was not a social being
but entirely solitary, and to this extent he agrees with Hobbes's account
of the state of nature. But in contrast to the English pessimist's view
that the life of man in such a condition must have been "poor, nasty, brutish
and short," Rousseau claims that original man, while admittedly solitary,
was healthy, happy, good, and free. The vices of men, he argues, date from
the time when men formed societies.
Rousseau
thus exonerates nature and blames society for the emergence of vices. He
says that passions that generate vices hardly exist in the state of nature
but begin to develop as soon as men form societies. Rousseau goes on to
suggest that societies started when men built their first huts, a development
that facilitated cohabitation of males and females; this in turn produced
the habit of living as a family and associating with neighbours. This "nascent
society,"
as Rousseau calls it, was good while it lasted; it was indeed the "golden
age" of human history. Only it did not endure. With the tender passion
of love there was also born the destructive passion of jealousy. Neighbours
started to compare their abilities and achievements with one another, and
this "marked the first step towards inequality and at the same time towards
vice." Men started to demand consideration and respect; their innocent
self-love turned into culpable pride, as each man wanted to be better than
everyone else.
The
introduction of property marked a further step toward inequality since
it made it necessary for men to institute law and government in order to
protect property. Rousseau laments the "fatal" concept of property in one
of his more eloquent passages, describing the "horrors" that have resulted
from men's departure from a condition in which the earth belonged to no
one. These passages in his second Discourse excited later revolutionaries
such as Marx and Lenin, but Rousseau himself did not think that the past
could be undone in any way; there was no point in men dreaming of a return
to the golden age.
Civil
society, as Rousseau describes it, comes into being to serve two purposes:
to provide peace for everyone and to ensure the right to property for anyone
lucky enough to have possessions. It is thus of some advantage to everyone,
but mostly to the advantage of the rich, since it transforms their de facto
ownership into rightful ownership and keeps the poor dispossessed. It is
a somewhat fraudulent social contract that introduces government since
the poor get so much less out of it than do the rich. Even so, the rich
are no happier in civil society than are the poor because social man is
never satisfied. Society leads men to hate one another to the extent that
their interests conflict, and the best they are able to do is to hide their
hostility behind a mask of courtesy. Thus Rousseau regards the inequality
between men not as a separate problem but as one of the features of the
long process by which men become alienated from nature and from innocence.
In
the dedication Rousseau wrote for the Discourse, in order to present it
to the republic of Geneva, he nevertheless praises that city-state for
having achieved the ideal balance between "the equality which nature established
among men and the inequality which they have instituted among themselves."
The arrangement he discerned in Geneva was one in which the best men were
chosen by the citizens and put in the highest positions of authority. Like
Plato, Rousseau always believed that a just society was one in which everyone
was in his right place. And having written the Discourse to explain how
men had lost their liberty in the past, he went on to write another book,
Du Contrat social (1762; The Social Contract), to suggest how they might
recover their liberty in the future. Again Geneva was the model; not Geneva
as it had become in 1754 when Rousseau returned there to recover his rights
as a citizen, but Geneva as it had once been; i.e., Geneva as Calvin had
designed it.
The
Social Contract begins with the sensational opening sentence: "Man was
born free, but he is everywhere in chains," and proceeds to argue that
men need not be in chains. If a civil society, or state, could be based
on a genuine social contract, as opposed to the fraudulent social contract
depicted in the Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, men would receive
in exchange for their independence a better kind of freedom, namely true
political, or republican, liberty. Such liberty is to be found in obedience
to a self-imposed law.
Rousseau's
definition of political liberty raises an obvious problem. For while it
can be readily agreed that an individual is free if he obeys only rules
he prescribes for himself, this is so because an individual is a person
with a single will. A society, by contrast, is a set of persons with a
set of individual wills, and conflict between separate wills is a fact
of universal experience. Rousseau's response to the problem is to define
his civil society as an artificial person united by a general will, or
volonté générale. The social contract that brings
society into being is a pledge, and the society remains in being as a pledged
group. Rousseau's republic is a creation of the general will--of a will
that never falters in each and every member to further the public, common,
or national interest--even though it may conflict at times with personal
interest.
Rousseau
sounds very much like Hobbes when he says that under the pact by which
men enter civil society everyone totally alienates himself and all his
rights to the whole community. Rousseau, however, represents this act as
a form of exchange of rights whereby men give up natural rights in return
for civil rights. The bargain is a good one because what men surrender
are rights of dubious value, whose realization depends solely on an individual
man's own might, and what they obtain in return are rights that are both
legitimate and enforced by the collective force of the community.
There
is no more haunting paragraph in The Social Contract than that in which
Rousseau speaks of "forcing a man to be free." But it would be wrong to
interpret these words in the manner of those critics who see Rousseau as
a prophet of modern totalitarianism. He does not claim that a whole society
can be forced to be free but only that an occasional individual, who is
enslaved by his passions to the extent of disobeying the law, can be restored
by force to obedience to the voice of the general will that exists inside
of him. The man who is coerced by society for a breach of the law is, in
Rousseau's view, being brought back to an awareness of his own true interests.
For
Rousseau there is a radical dichotomy between true law and actual law.
Actual law, which he describes in the Discourse on the Origin of Inequality,
simply protects the status quo. True law, as described in The Social Contract,
is just law, and what ensures its being just is that it is made by the
people in its collective capacity as sovereign and obeyed by the same people
in their individual capacities as subjects. Rousseau is confident that
such laws could not be unjust because it is inconceivable that any people
would make unjust laws for itself.
Rousseau
is, however, troubled by the fact that the majority of a people does not
necessarily represent its most intelligent citizens. Indeed, he agrees
with Plato that most people are stupid. Thus the general will, while always
morally sound, is sometimes mistaken. Hence Rousseau suggests the people
need a lawgiver--a great mind like Solon or Lycurgus or Calvin--to draw
up a constitution and system of laws. He even suggests that such lawgivers
need to claim divine inspiration in order to persuade the dim-witted multitude
to accept and endorse the laws it is offered.
This
suggestion echoes a similar proposal by Machiavelli, a political theorist
Rousseau greatly admired and whose love of republican government he shared.
An even more conspicuously Machiavellian influence can be discerned in
Rousseau's chapter on civil religion, where he argues that Christianity,
despite its truth, is useless as a republican religion on the grounds that
it is directed to the unseen world and does nothing to teach citizens the
virtues that are needed in the service of the state, namely, courage, virility,
and patriotism. Rousseau does not go so far as Machiavelli in proposing
a revival of pagan cults, but he does propose a civil religion with minimal
theological content designed to fortify and not impede (as Christianity
impedes) the cultivation of martial virtues. It is understandable that
the authorities of Geneva, profoundly convinced that the national church
of their little republic was at the same time a truly Christian church
and a nursery of patriotism, reacted angrily against this chapter in Rousseau's
Social Contract.
By
the year 1762, however, when The Social Contract was published, Rousseau
had given up any thought of settling in Geneva. After recovering his citizen's
rights in 1754, he had returned to Paris and the company of his friends
around the Encyclopédie. But he became increasingly ill at ease
in such worldly society and began to quarrel with his fellow Philosophes.
An article for the Encyclopédie on the subject of Geneva, written
by d'Alembert at Voltaire's instigation, upset Rousseau partly by suggesting
that the pastors of the city had lapsed from Calvinist severity into unitarian
laxity and partly by proposing that a theatre should be erected there.
Rousseau hastened into print with a defense of the Calvinist orthodoxy
of the pastors and with an elaborate attack on the theatre as an institution
that could only do harm to an innocent community such as Geneva.
Years
of seclusion and exile.
By
the time his Lettre à d'Alembert sur les spectacles (1758; Letter
to Monsieur d'Alembert on the Theatre) appeared in print, Rousseau had
already left Paris to pursue a life closer to nature on the country estate
of his friend Mme d'Épinay near Montmorency. When the hospitality
of Mme d'Épinay proved to entail much the same social round as that
of Paris, Rousseau retreated to a nearby cottage, called Montlouis, under
the protection of the Maréchal de Luxembourg. But even this highly
placed friend could not save him in 1762 when his treatise on education,
Émile, was published and scandalized the pious Jansenists of the
French Parlements even as The Social Contract scandalized the Calvinists
of Geneva. In Paris, as in Geneva, they ordered the book to be burned and
the author arrested; all the Maréchal de Luxembourg could do was
to provide a carriage for Rousseau to escape from France. Rousseau spent
the rest of his life as a fugitive moving from one refuge to another.
The
years at Montmorency had been the most productive of his literary career;
besides The Social Contract and Émile, Julie: ou, la nouvelle Héloïse
(1761; Julie: or, The New Eloise) came out within 12 months, all three
works of seminal importance. The New Eloise, being a novel, escaped the
censorship to which the other two works were subject; indeed of all his
books it proved to be the most widely read and the most universally praised
in his lifetime. It develops the Romanticism that had already informed
his writings on music and perhaps did more than any other single work of
literature to influence the spirit of its age. It made the author at least
as many friends among the reading public--and especially among educated
women--as The Social Contract and Émile made enemies among magistrates
and priests. If it did not exempt him from persecution, at least it ensured
that his persecution was observed, and admiring femmes du monde intervened
from time to time to help him so that Rousseau was never, unlike Voltaire
and Diderot, actually imprisoned.
The
theme of The New Eloise provides a striking contrast to that of The Social
Contract. It is about people finding happiness in domestic as distinct
from public life, in the family as opposed to the state. The central character,
Saint-Preux, is a middle-class preceptor who falls in love with his upper-class
pupil, Julie. She returns his love and yields to his advances, but the
difference between their classes makes marriage between them impossible.
Baron d'Étange, Julie's father, has indeed promised her to a fellow
nobleman named Wolmar. As a dutiful daughter, Julie marries Wolmar and
Saint-Preux goes off on a voyage around the world with an English aristocrat,
Bomston, from whom he acquires a certain stoicism. Julie succeeds in forgetting
her feelings for Saint-Preux and finds happiness as wife, mother, and chatelaine.
Some six years later Saint-Preux returns from his travels and is engaged
as tutor to the Wolmar children. All live together in harmony, and there
are only faint echoes of the old affair between Saint-Preux and Julie.
The little community, dominated by Julie, illustrates one of Rousseau's
political principles: that while men should rule the world in public life,
women should rule men in private life. At the end of The New Eloise, when
Julie has made herself ill in an attempt to rescue one of her children
from drowning, she comes face-to-face with a truth about herself: that
her love for Saint-Preux has never died.
The
novel was clearly inspired by Rousseau's own curious relationship--at once
passionate and platonic--with Sophie d'Houdetot, a noblewoman who lived
near him at Montmorency. He himself asserted in the Confessions (1781-88)
that he was led to write the book by "a desire for loving, which I had
never been able to satisfy and by which I felt myself devoured." Saint-Preux's
experience of love forbidden by the laws of class reflects Rousseau's own
experience; and yet it cannot be said that The New Eloise is an attack
on those laws, which seem, on the contrary, to be given the status almost
of laws of nature. The members of the Wolmar household are depicted as
finding happiness in living according to an aristocratic ideal. They appreciate
the routines of country life and enjoy the beauties of the Swiss and Savoyard
Alps. But despite such an endorsement of the social order, the novel was
revolutionary; its very free expression of emotions and its extreme sensibility
deeply moved its large readership and profoundly influenced literary developments.
Émile
is a book that seems to appeal alternately to the republican ethic of The
Social Contract and the aristocratic ethic of The New Eloise. It is also
halfway between a novel and a didactic essay. Described by the author as
a treatise on education, it is not about schooling but about the upbringing
of a rich man's son by a tutor who is given unlimited authority over him.
At the same time the book sets out to explore the possibilities of an education
for republican citizenship. The basic argument of the book, as Rousseau
himself expressed it, is that vice and error, which are alien to a child's
original nature, are introduced by external agencies, so that the work
of a tutor must always be directed to counteracting those forces by manipulating
pressures that will work with nature and not against it. Rousseau devotes
many pages to explaining the methods the tutor must use. These methods
involve a noticeable measure of deceit, and although corporal punishment
is forbidden, mental cruelty is not.
Whereas
The Social Contract is concerned with the problems of achieving freedom,
Émile is concerned with achieving happiness and wisdom. In this
different context religion plays a different role. Instead of a civil religion,
Rousseau here outlines a personal religion, which proves to be a kind of
simplified Christianity, involving neither revelation nor the familiar
dogmas of the church. In the guise of La Profession de foi du vicaire savoyard
(1765; The Profession of Faith of a Savoyard Vicar) Rousseau sets out what
may fairly be regarded as his own religious views, since that book confirms
what he says on the subject in his private correspondence. Rousseau could
never entertain doubts about God's existence or about the immortality of
the soul. He felt, moreover, a strong emotional drive toward the worship
of God, whose presence he felt most forcefully in nature, especially in
mountains and forests untouched by the hand of man. He also attached great
importance to conscience, the "divine voice of the soul in man," opposing
this both to the bloodless categories of rationalistic ethics and to the
cold tablets of biblical authority.
This
minimal creed put Rousseau at odds with the orthodox adherents of the churches
and with the openly atheistic Philosophes of Paris, so that despite the
enthusiasm that some of his writings, and especially The New Eloise, excited
in the reading public, he felt himself increasingly isolated, tormented,
and pursued. After he had been expelled from France, he was chased from
canton to canton in Switzerland. He reacted to the suppression of The Social
Contract in Geneva by indicting the regime of that city-state in a pamphlet
entitled Lettres écrites de la montagne (1764; Letters Written from
the Mountain). No longer, as in the Discourse on the Origin of Inequality,
was Geneva depicted as a model republic but as one that had been taken
over by "twenty-five despots"; the subjects of the king of England were
said to be free men by comparison with the victims of Genevan tryranny.
It
was in England that Rousseau found refuge after he had been banished from
the canton of Bern. The Scottish philosopher David Hume took him there
and secured the offer of a pension from King George III; but once in England,
Rousseau became aware that certain British intellectuals were making fun
of him, and he suspected Hume of participating in the mockery. Various
symptoms of paranoia began to manifest themselves in Rousseau, and he returned
to France incognito. Believing that Thérèse was the only
person he could rely on, he finally married her in 1768, when he was 56
years old.
The
last decade.
In
the remaining 10 years of his life Rousseau produced primarily autobiographical
writings, mostly intended to justify himself against the accusations of
his adversaries. The most important was his Confessions, modeled on the
work of the same title by St. Augustine and achieving something of the
same classic status. He also wrote Rousseau juge de Jean-Jacques (1780;
"Rousseau, Judge of Jean-Jacques") to reply to specific charges by his
enemies and Les Rêveries du promeneur solitaire (1782; Reveries of
the Solitary Walker), one of the most moving of his books, in which the
intense passion of his earlier writings gives way to a gentle lyricism
and serenity. And indeed, Rousseau does seem to have recovered his peace
of mind in his last years, when he was once again afforded refuge on the
estates of great French noblemen, first the Prince de Conti and then the
Marquis de Girardin, in whose park at Ermenonville he died on July 2, 1778.
"Discourse
Upon the Origin and Foundation of the Inequality Among Mankind, A," or
"Discours sur l'origine et les fondements de l'inégalité
parmi les hommes," or "Second Discours" (work by Rousseau)
The
background and influence of naturalism.
Pietists
emphasized Christian devotion and diligence as paths to the good life;
Enlightenment thinkers focused on reason and clear thinking as the sensible
way to happiness. Rousseau and his followers were intrigued by a third
and more elusive ideal: naturalism. Rousseau, in his A Discourse on Inequality,
an account of the historical development of the human race, distinguished
between "natural man" (man as formed by nature) and "social man" (man as
shaped by society). He argued that good education should develop the nature
of man. Yet Rousseau found that mankind has not one nature but several:
man originally lived in a "pure state of nature" but was altered by changes
beyond control and took on a different nature; this nature, in turn, was
changed as man became social. The creation of the arts and sciences caused
man to become "less pure," more artificial, and egoistic, and man's egoistic
nature prevents him from regaining the simplicity of original human nature.
Rousseau is pessimistic, almost fatalistic, about changing the nature of
modern man.
Émile,
his major work on education, describes an attempt to educate a simple and
pure natural child for life in a world from which social man is estranged.
Émile is removed from man's society to a little society inhabited
only by the child and his tutor. Social elements enter the little society
through the tutor's knowledge when the tutor thinks Émile can learn
something from them. Rousseau's aim throughout is to show how a natural
education, unlike the artificial and formal education of society, enables
Émile to become social, moral, and rational while remaining true
to his original nature. Because Émile is educated to be a man, not
a priest, a soldier, or an attorney, he will be able to do what is needed
in any situation.
The
first book of Émile describes the period from birth to learning
to speak. The most important thing for the healthy and natural development
of the child at this age is that he learn to use his physical powers, especially
the sense organs. The teacher must pay special attention to distinguishing
between the real needs of the child and his whims and fancies. The second
book covers the time from the child's learning to speak to the age of 12.
Games and other forms of amusement should be allowed at this age, and the
child should by no means be overtaxed by scholarly instruction at too early
an age. The child Émile is to learn through experience, not through
words; he is to bow not to the commands of man but to necessities. The
third book is devoted to the ages from 12 to 15. This is the time of learning,
not from books of course but from the "book of the world." Émile
must gain knowledge in concrete situations provided by his tutor. He learns
a trade, among other things. He studies science, not by receiving instruction
in its facts but by making the instruments necessary to solve scientific
problems of a practical sort. Not until the age of 15, described in the
fourth book, does Émile study the history of man and social experience
and thus encounter the world of morals and conscience. During this stage
Émile is on the threshold of social maturity and the "age of reason."
Finally, he marries and, his education over, tells his tutor that the only
chains he knows are those of necessity and that he will thus be free anywhere
on earth.
The
final book describes the education of Sophie, the girl who marries Émile.
In Rousseau's view, the education of girls was to be similar with regard
to naturalness, but it differed because of sexual differences. A girl cannot
be educated to be a man. According to Rousseau, a woman should be the centre
of the family, a housewife, and a mother. She should strive to please her
husband, concern herself more than he with having a good reputation, and
be satisfied with a simple religion of the emotions. Because her intellectual
education is not of the essence, "her studies must all be on the practical
side."
At
the close of Émile, Rousseau cannot assure the reader that Émile
and Sophie will be happy when they live apart from the tutor; the outcome
of his experiment is in doubt, even in his own mind. Even so, probably
no other writer in modern times has inspired as many generations as did
Rousseau. His dramatic portrayal of the estrangement of natural man from
society jolted and influenced such contemporary thinkers as Immanuel Kant
and continues to intrigue philosophers and social scientists. His idea
that teachers must see things as children do inspired Pestalozzi and has
endured as a much-imitated ideal. Finally, his emphasis on understanding
the child's nature had a profound influence by creating interest in the
study of child development, inspiring the work of such psychologists as
G. Stanley Hall and Jean Piaget.
Copyright
1994-1998 Encyclopaedia Britannica
Academic
Year 00-01
07/02/2001
©a.r.e.a.
Dr. Vicente Forés López
©Ana
Aroa Alba Cuesta
Universitat
de València Press