Chesterton as an Essayist
Principally, I
have decided to work about this author because he is a very constant person in
relation to his work, and even sometimes he affords to give some advices to his lectors.
In the article
“A Defence of Rash Vows” –an abridged version of a chapter in his book
“The Defendant”, 1903- Chesterton tries to find a reason to explain a insanity
or senseless oath made by men very often, as it happens with lovers and the marriage. This is a point which
leads the writer to introduce a matter related to religion and, therefore,
deepening in his Christian beliefs as a result of his previous conversion
(which took place in 1922): “The revolt against vows has been carried in our
day even to the extent of a revolt against the typical vow of marriage. It is
most amusing to listen to the opponents of marriage on this subject. They
appear to imagine that the ideal of constancy was a yoke mysteriously imposed
on mankind by the devil, instead of being, as it is, a yoke consistently
imposed by all lovers on themselves. They have invented a phrase, a phrase that
is a black and white contradiction in two words –‘free-love’- as if a lover ever
had been, or ever could be, free. It is the nature of love to bind itself, and
the institution of marriage merely paid the average man the compliment of
taking him at his word. Modern sages offer to the lover, with an ill-favoured
grin, the largest liberties and the fullest irresponsibility; but they do not
respect him as the old Church respected him; they do not write his oath upon
the heavens, as the record of his highest moment. They give him every liberty
except the liberty to sell his liberty, which is the only one that he wants”.
On the other hand, Chesterton compares
today’s men with “the decadents” –not men who did things which were
decadent, but “belonged generally to the most robust classes of what is
generally accepted as a robust age (...) ‘For he that lives more lives than
one, More deaths that one must die’: At the end of all this is that maddening
horror of unreality which descends upon the decadents”. Here we can get
aware of the author’s opposition to modern errors like the industrial and
capitalist civilisation, which he solves claiming for the social ideal from the
Middle Ages. As an example of this, let’s have a look at the following
statement: “The man who makes a vow makes an appointment with himself at
some distant time or place. The danger of it is that himself should not keep
the appointment. And in modern times this terror of one’s self, of the weakness
and mutability of one’s self, has perilously increased, and is the real basis
of the objection to vows of any kind”.
In short, he
justifies the fact of making “rash vows” as an impulse to release
oneself: “To be everlasting passing through dangers which we cannot scare
us, to be taking oaths which we know cannot bind us, to defying enemies who we
know cannot conquer us –this is the grinning tyranny of decadence which is
called freedom”. Besides, he adds: “The man who made a vow, however
wild, gave a healthy and natural expression to the greatness of a great moment (...)
And the withering consciousness that he did not mean what he said, that he was,
in truth, saying nothing of any great import, would take from him exactly that
sense of daring actuality which is the excitement of a vow”. That’s the way
he shows what forces a person to promise something; and we indeed can proof it
with his sentence: “Everywhere there is the persistent and insane attempt to
obtain pleasure without paying for it”. Although it’s obvious his
conclusion is more flat: “All around us is the city of small sins, abounding
in backways and retreats, but surely, sooner or later, the towering flame will
rise from the harbour announcing that the reign of the cowards is over and a
man is burning his ships”. Resuming, we could say this writing deals with
rash promises and tells us why they should be made and kept. Apart from that,
it would also be at our disposal the consideration of making imprudent
decisions up because of one’s worrying for being successful in the living society.
If we continue
to investigate the labour of this writer as an essayist, we could glance at his
article “A Piece of Chalk”, extracted from an essay in “Tremendous
Trifles”. The original essay appeared in the Daily News (the newspaper for
which he worked) on November the 4th, 1905. This one is useful for
Chesterton to reflect once more the importance of the purity “of the best
religious morality, of real Christianity” from the mere range of colours,
for, as he says, “the chief assertion of religious morality is that white is
a colour (...) God paints in many colours; but He never paints so gorgeously, I
had almost said so gaudily, as when He paints in white. In a sense our age has
realised this fact, and expressed it in our sullen costume. For if it were
really true that white was a blank and colourless thing, negative and
non-committal, then white would be used instead of black and grey for the
funereal dress of this pessimistic period. Which is not the case”. As it
can be proved, morality is always present, but what is extraordinary and more
impressive is how the composer joins the moral stuff to some simple things such
as colours themselves –but, of course, he bears in mind the white colour and
its plainness and authenticity at all times: “(...) as I sat scrawling these
silly figures on the brown paper, it began to dawn on me, to my great disgust,
that I had left one chalk, and that a most exquisite and essential chalk,
behind. I searched all my pockets, but I could not find any white chalk. Now,
those who are acquainted with all the philosophy (nay, religion) which is
typified in the art of drawing on brown paper, know that white is positive and
essential. I cannot avoid remarking here upon a moral significance”. By the
way, let’s emphasise Chesterton’s words when saying “...philosophy (nay,
religion)...”; this demonstrates his preference for the religion before the
‘science’ related to some famous characters likes Charles
Dickens, a philosopher who was severely criticised by him (even he wrote a
critical book against this person, in 1906). Anyway, our English writer seems
to fall into the arms of philosophy at the end of this essay, when he concludes
revealing: “And I stood there in a trance of pleasure, realising that this
Southern England is not only a grand peninsula, and a tradition and a
civilisation; it is something even more admirable. It is a piece of chalk”,
creating, thus, a masterly metaphor which gives the name to the composition.
That’s why it lets us say that nothing, somehow, manages to be everything.
And, to go on
with this literary taste our last affirmation has left, we’d better look upon
another essay called “Concerning a Strange City”, which is included into
“The Common Man”, originally in The New
Witness (11-25-21). In fact, the author talks about “the power of words”,
as the article starts so: “Everyone has his own private and almost secret
selection among the example of the mysterious power of words, the power which a
certain verbal combination has over the emotions and even the soul”. More
in advance, the reader is able to find out a certain contrast between poetry
and prose: “The great lines of the poets are like landscapes or visions, but
the same strange light can be found not only in the high places of poetry but
also in quite obscure corners of prose”. Once we have read it, it would not
be very difficult to deduce he’s defending his own genre, I mean, his own way
of writing and, so, his way of expression: “I can only express what I mean
by saying that it is the finite part of the image that really suggests
infinity”. Moreover, some philosophical sketches may be noticed too: “In
the mind of man, if not in the nature of things, there seems to be some
connection between concentration and reality (...) there has always been this
spearlike selection and concentration in man’s conception of higher things.
Compared with that, there is something not only vague but vulgar in most of the
talk about infinity. (...) this infinity is the enemy of all that is fine”.
Apart from
that, as the same Chesterton quotes, there are “philological points”
drawn in the mentioned text: “(...) most things that are fine are finite. (...)
All fine things are in this sense finished, even when they are eternal”. Finally,
we are immersed in a world which has to do with the relationship between Poetry
and Religion; that is explained in these words: “Poetry is committed to this
concentration fully as much as religion (...) And if religion were removed
tomorrow, the poets would only begin to act as the pagans acted”. To sum up
all what has been exposed above, we could say in this essay Religion, Poetry
and Philosophy are joined but, at the same time, distinguished as far as we are
concerned after reading it. Gilbert Keith touches briefly the different points
here and is trying to make his readers acquire the same kind of knowledge and morality, if we take into account the philosophy he describes.
Precisely in
another of his writings titled “Negative and Positive Morality”
-published in Illustrated London News (ILN) on January the 3rd,
1920- he also makes reference to the morality, although it is a special one in
this case: the religious morality. We understand it when we go over the
argument, which begins telling so: “The silliest sort of progressive
complains of negative morality, and compares it unfavourably with positive
morality. (...) To desire the construction of something is to desire the
destruction of whatever prevents its construction”. Then, after having done
such an introduction, our author clears up that “This is particularly plain
in the fuss about the ‘negative’ morality of the Ten Commandments. The truth is
that the curtness of the Commandments is an evidence, not of the gloom and
narrowness of a religion but of its liberality and humanity. (...) In
comparison with this positive morality, the Ten Commandments rather shine in
that brevity which is the soul of wit ” –let’s remark this last term, for
we are told how important the Commandments are for every Christian and,
therefore, for this converted person, and equally the primal shortness of the
optimistic moral. Once we have made a mention of Christendom’s Ten
Commandments, we could link it to the idea of the Seven Deadly Sins, what indeed reflects a
profound morality.
So far so good;
but, however, the type of negative morality is found against this positive one
and here the trouble comes up: “Negative morality is positive morality,
stated in the plainest and therefore the most positive way”. Then we have
reached the polemic: is this true? To answer that, Chesterton takes as an
instance a particular case: somebody called Mr Robinson’s slaughter (what
supposes to constitute a violent narration with an end that eventually remains
as sympathetic): “If I am told not to murder Mr Robinson, if I am stopped in
the very act of murdering Mr Robinson, it is obvious that Mr Robinson is not
only spared, but in a sense renewed, and even created. And those who like Mr
Robinson, among them my reactionary romanticism might suggest the inclusion of
Mrs Robinson, will be well aware that they have recovered a living and complex
unity”. To be more concrete, we are being informed of the writer’s
idealism, a sort of revolutionary Romanticism that gives turn immediately to
the Christianity and its consequent religious outlines again: “(...) those
who like European civilisation, and the common code of what used to be called
Christendom, will realise that salvation is not negative, but highly positive,
and even highly complex. (...) Nothing is negative except nothing. It is not
our rescue that was negative, but only nothingness and annihilation from which
we were rescued”. It must not be necessary to name the intention of the
novelist here, as the expression “rescued” shows sincerely the meaning
of the context, as well as the following paragraph: “When our hopes for the
coming time seem disturbed or doubtful, and peace chaotic, let us remember that
it is really our disappointment that is an illusion. It is our rescue that is a
reality. Our grounds for gratitude are really far greater than our powers of
being grateful” -one more time, the religious beliefs are patent here, as
the expression “being grateful” indicates; an undoubted strong belief
supported by the pun in the latest assertion: “We adorn things most when we
love them most. And we love them most when we have nearly lost them”-.
Not strictly
morality but rather scepticism is the main point in a different creation from
this author named “The Extraordinary Cabman”, which first appeared in
London’s Daily News and was later collected in the volume of essays “Tremendous
Trifles”; if we talk a bit more about it, we should say Chesterton’s aim here
is the philosophical question of reality represented by his hating towards
sceptic people, especially some contemporary men like George Bernard Shaw
(presumably one of his friends at the meeting in the course of the article).
This sort of scepticism provokes the entrance for metaphysic matters in this
issue, as follows: “(...) the question is whether a man can be certain of
anything at all. I think he can be certain, for if (...) it is impossible
intellectually to entertain certainty, what is this certainty which it is
impossible to entertain? If I have never experienced such a thing as certainty
I cannot even say that a thing is not certain”. And, indeed, such is the
importance of this focusing that he says himself: “(...) metaphysics is the
only thoroughly emotional thing”.
According to
what we are able to read, Chesterton wanders through his imagination as he
fancies a cabman –who is driving him and has had a misunderstanding with him-
isn’t certainly human: without any doubt, he is a very special character
because he has a frightful expression on his face but he’s completely honest,
G.K. thinks.
In another way,
we might submerge in a queer atmosphere of confusion when he explains that “The
exciting question for real scepticism is whether we possess past life”, but
it is merely a parenthetical comment made in order to guide the own reader
before the sceptics’ supposition that we possess a future life. Along the
essay, nevertheless, Chesterton shows his political beliefs when revealing “I
believe in Democracy” or “I believe in free will”,or even “I
believe in fixed character of virtue”.
Let’s go on
having a look at “The Shop of Ghosts”, which is also included in “Tremendous
Trifles”, after having been published in London’s Daily News. This is a parable
about Christmas and, as it is logic, the enormous religiosity
invading this writer is obvious with the starring of Father Christmas, who
turns out to be immortal –Mr Charles Dickens, who takes part in the action too,
addresses him saying: “I understand it now (...) you will never die”,
and then the essay is finished. But, further away, we take note of the present
opposition to the modern world: G.K. expresses “I am a democrat; I know I am
out of fashion in the modern world”. In addition, Father Christmas in
person says: “They seem to object to me on such curious and inconsistent
sort of grounds, these scientific men, and these innovators” / “These
modern people are living and I am dead” -to what the same author, principal
role in the story, replies: “You may be dead (...) But as for what they are
doing, do not call it living”. Lastly, let’s highlight the notable
mysticism in this paragraph: “in some strange way, the mental cure did not
seem to be final. There was still in my mind an unmanageable something that
told me that I had strayed into some odd atmosphere, or that I had already done
some odd thing. I felt as if I had worked a miracle or committed a sin. It was
as if I had, at any rate, stepped across some border in my soul” –this may
permit us to join the chastity described at the beginning of this summarise.
And this kind of mysticism gathers the one developed in “Babies” (from
the essay “In Defence of Baby Worship”, which just exposes his meaning only by
pronouncing its title; it was taken from “The Defendant”, 1903), where we find
a strong contrast between common sense and a presumed mysticism: “The most
unfathomable schools and sages have never attained to the gravity which dwells
in the eyes of a baby of three months old. It is the gravity of astonishment at
the universe, and astonishment at the universe is not mysticism, but a
transcendent common sense”. Altogether, we have the same impression of
Christianity when it is told that “As we walk the streets and see below us
those delightful bulbous heads, three times too big for the body, which mark
these heads there is a new universe, as new as it was on the seventh day of
creation”; same sensation that is felt in this other example: “When we
look upon lives so human and yet so small... we feel the same kind of
obligation to these creatures that >God< might feel... (...) >They<
give us the most perfect hint of the humour that awaits us in the kingdom of
heaven”.
The mysticism
we had named before is now introduced more clearly: “The essential rectitude
of our view of children lies in the fact that we feel them and their ways to be
supernatural while, for some mysterious reason, we do not feel ourselves or our
own ways to be supernatural”. Finally, it would also be interesting to look
at the relationship, composed by him, between those small creatures and grown
up people –it becomes, nay, a clever comparison: “But the influence of
children goes further than its first trifling effort of remarking heaven and
earth. It forces us actually to remodel our conduct in accordance with this
revolutionary theory of the marvellousness of all things. We do actually treat
talking in children as marvellous, walking in children as marvellous, common
intelligence in children as marvellous...>and< that attitude towards
children is right. It is our attitude towards grown up people that is wrong”.
Related to “The
Shop of Ghosts” and, maybe, to “Babies” too in what respects to religion, is “Christmas
and the First Games”, which takes part in the book “The Coloured Lands”.
Here G.K. exposes the meaning of the essay at the beginning, when he reveals: “I
have sometimes been haunted with a vague story about a wild and fantastic
uncle, the enemy of parents and the cause of revolution in nurseries, who went
about preaching a certain theory; I mean the theory that all the objects which
children use at Christmas for what we call riotous or illegitimate purposes, were
originally created for those purposes; and not for the humdrum household
purposes which they now serve”. If analysing what he says this time, we
could touch the subject which provokes such a polemic confrontation in our
current society: the consumerism that invades those
compulsive and other not so compulsive buyers when Christmas holiday come. “I
cannot set forth here in any great detail any actual proofs of these
prehistoric origins; but I never heard of anybody bothering about proofs in
connection with prehistoric origins (...) Nobody expects any historic evidence
for things of this sort, because they are prehistoric; and nobody dreams of
attempting to found them on any scientific facts; they are simply Science. I do
not see why my favourite uncle and I should not be Science too. I do not see
why we should not simply make things up out of our own heads; things which
cannot possibly be contradicted, just as they cannot possibly be proved”.
For this case, we should take into consideration Chesterton’s speaking about
scientific aspects: it is not his speciality but that’s why he does not get
entangled in the matter and just explains the fact that someone can’t cast
doubt on something if he/she can’t prove it. This may drive us up to morality
questions again. However, the essayist does not let himself go influenced by
such a subject anew and he leaders a criticism now towards modern prose writers
of his time, such as Dr Freud: “The only difference is that my uncle and I,
especially when we set out with a general intention of talking about Christmas,
cannot manage to work up that curious loathing of the human race, which is now
considered essential to any history written for humanitarians. Dr Freud (as is
perhaps natural after a heavy day of psychopathic interviews) seems to have
taken quite a dislike to human beings. So when he makes up the story of how
their first forgotten institutions arose in utterly unrecorded times, he makes
the family story as nasty as he can; like any other modern novelist. But my
uncle and I (especially at Christmas) happen to feel in a more cheerful and
charitable frame of mind; -let’s emphasise the word ‘charitable’, which
tends to be connected to Christmas dates but is actually senseless by the
beginning of the 20th century as well as now, already a hundred
years afterwards- (...) and, as there are no iron creeds or dogmas to
restrain anybody from anything, we have as much right to imagine cheerful
things as he has to imagine gloomy ones. And we beg to announce, with the same
authority, that everything began with a celestial pillow fight of cherubs, or
that the whole world was made entirely for the games of children”. As a
consequence of his saying, he can deduce he ranks equally with the mentioned doctor,
for taking an example.
Following that
we come across a short paragraph where he sets out the points which show the
authenticity of his uncle’s beliefs: “The two or three truths, of which my
uncle’s hypothesis is at least symbolic or suggestive, may be conveniently
arranged thus. First, it must always be remembered that there really is a
mystery, and something resembling a religious mystery, in the origin of many
things which have since become (very rightly) practical and (very wrongly)
prosaic (...) Second, it must be remembered that these rituals, including
Christmas, have been on the whole preserved by the populace; for a true
populace is far more traditional than an aristocracy. They have been preserved
by poor people, though generally by poor people who possessed some small
property, in short, most markedly by a peasantry”. Precisely in harmony
with the countrymen we have at our disposal another essay of him under the name
of “The Gardener and the Guinea”; Chesterton deals here with the English
Peasantry, whom he devotes a kind worship, and talks about their characteristic
at the very first moment (equality, community, co-operation and common laws)
and names the country gardener as the example which best takes after the
English peasant: “Strictly speaking, there is no such thing as an English
Peasant. Indeed, the type can only exist in community, so much it depend on
co-operation and common laws (...) you cannot have a Peasant till you have a
peasantry. The essence of the Peasant ideal is equality; and you cannot be
equal all by yourself. Nevertheless, because human nature always craves and
half creates the things necessary to its happiness, there are approximations
and suggestions of the possibility of such a race even here. The nearest approach
I know to the temper of a Peasant in England is that of the country gardener”.
Immediately after, G.K. tells us a story which consists of a parable that
occurred to him. In it, a gardener who was working on his ground found a golden
coin, a pure Spade Guinea of the Georges. Chesterton said to him to keep it –as
the same gardener had found it-; at first, the worker thought of making a
brooch for his wife but later he brought it back to our writer because he
wasn’t feeling happy with it: as the author writes, “I could not get a ray
of light on the reason of his refusal; but he looked lowering and unhappy. Had
he some mystical instinct that it is just such accidental and irrational wealth
that is the doom of all peasantries? Perhaps he dimly felt that the boy’s
pirate tales are true; and that buried treasure is a thing for robbers and not
for producers. Perhaps he thought there was a curse on such capital: on the
coal of the coal-owners, on the gold of the gold-seekers. Perhaps there is”.
In the last analysis, we are bound to face the next expression: “(...) at
least I know that it needs a man to make a garden; a man whose name is Adam”,
what forces us to make allusion of the Christianity obvious in this case again.
At any rate,
it’s possible for the lectors to prove that Gilbert Keith can’t only talk about
morality, religiousness and mysticism; besides, he demonstrated his agile
capacity for undertaking some distinct affairs such as the one in which “Asparagus”
is based on: the English class system and its fads. To begin with this
composition, which was written by Chesterton on June the 18th, 1914,
for “New Witness”, there’s an evident similarity between asparagus and the
noble families. At first, asparagus seem to be an incomprehensible complement
to relate to the aim in this article, but we are likely to realise why the
author did so after glancing at the initial words: “We might say of sticks
of asparagus that they have often lost their heads, and we might say the same
of aristocrats. Both heads have been bitten off by the guillotine before now.
But to complete the parallel we must maintain that the head of the aristocrat
was the best part of him; and this is often hard to maintain”. More
concretely and profoundly, G.K. confesses: “But, indeed, I do not base the
view upon any such fancies from phraseology. Far deeper in earth are the roots
of asparagus. The one essential of an aristocracy is to be in advance of its
age. (...) There must be a password”.
In a more
practical and materialistic manner, Chesterton tries to remark the importance
of the asparagus and their simplicity to be eaten: “The working instance
best known to us of the middle classes is the old arbitrary distinction about
how to eat asparagus .Now, excluding cannibalism and the habit of eating sand
(about which I can offer no opinion) there is really nothing one can eat which
is less fitted to be eaten with the fingers than asparagus (...) it doesn’t
want any holding up. We will not exaggerate. (...) while strictly avoiding
anything like exaggeration or frivolity, I still note that the point of
asparagus is that it is not the food, among other foods, specially fitted to
the fingers. (...) It could not have been custom: that is why it was etiquette”.
Changing with
what it has been exposed above, and continuing with the nobles, we reach the
result of the aristocratic Futurism or, as it’s well-known, Progress: “Tennyson,
who was too much touched with this aristocratic –or snobbish- Futurism, wrote,
‘Lest one good custom should corrupt the world’, which really means lest
everybody should learn the right way of eating asparagus. And so, out of luxury
and waste and weariness, the fever they call Progress came into the world”.
As a form of conclusion, we find: “They have changed the password”, he means,
a change into the English class system.
Dealing with a different business, we face the essay
known as “How I found the Superman”, which occurs to be a satire on the
Nietzchian Superman and in which our author configures a critic against some
modern writers such as Shaw and Mr Wells, starting so: “Readers of Mr
Bernard Shaw and other modern writers may be interested to know that the
Superman has been found. I found him; he lives in South Croydon. My success
will be a great blow to Mr Shaw, who has been following quite a false scent,
and is now looking for the creature in Blackpool; and as for Mr Wells’ notion
of generating him out of gases in a private laboratory I always thought it
doomed to failure”. Then, all what has been mentioned is followed by a
political matter: “(...) daring experiments in Neo-Individualist Eugenics
(...) are now the one absorbing interest of the English democracy (...)”.
Moreover, we are told about Superman’s parents; as far as his father, Dr Hagg,
concerns, we have:“(...) he became one of our greatest geologists; and
achieved that bold and bright outlook upon the future of Socialism which only
geology can give. At first there seems something like a rift, a faint, but
perceptible, fissure, between his views and those of his aristocratic wife”
–let’s take notice of Lady Hypatia Hagg’s social class, the aristocracy, which
has also been commented previously. This way, we can observe a contrast between
the marriage of Superman’s parents: a geologist (him) and an aristocrat (her),
which brings the birth of the Superman as an outcome: “(...) the married
pair perceived an essential union in the unmistakably modern character of both
their views; and in this enlightening and comprehensive expression their souls
found peace. The result is that this union of the two highest types of our
civilisation, the fashionable lady and all but vulgar medical man, has been
blessed by the birth of the Superman, that being whom all the labourers in
Battersea are so eagerly expecting night and day (...) the creature who was
more marvellous than the children of men”.
After
Superman’s death, Chesterton describes something unnatural in the funeral: “As
I walked away from Croydon that night I saw men in black carrying out a coffin
that was not of any human shape”; what is more, he qualifies the funeral as
“cosmic”. And, once described the whole situation, he finishes telling
the reader that “I thought that there was a hoot of laughter in the high
wail of the wind”, which let –at least for me- deduce a little mark of
irony and, therefore, satire in general. Perhaps it would be interesting to say
this article appeared in Daily News (1909).
The next essay
I’m bound to analyse is “On American Morals”. It is about American Puritanism and it’s outstanding enough the description we find
of the moral mind of this Continent, which is supposed to be a mix between
feebleness and insignificance: “America is sometimes offered to us, even by Americans
(who ought to know better) as a moral example. There are indeed very real
American virtues; but this virtuous attitude is hardly one of them”. That
is exactly what precedes a critic to cultural critics such as Miss Avis D.
Carlson: “And if anyone wants to know whether a welter of weakness and
inconsequence the moral of America can sometimes be, he may be advised to look,
not so much to the Crime Wage or the Charleston, as to the serious idealistic
essays by highbrows and cultural critics”.
Another chief
point in this article may be the wrong of the standard of abstract right and
wrong for the Americans; this is explained to us with the following terms: “The
standard of abstract right and wrong apparently is this. That a girl by smoking
a cigarette makes herself one of the company of the fiends of hell. That such
an action is much the same as that of a sexual vampire. That a young man who
continues to drink fermented liquor must necessarily be ‘evil’ and must deny
the very existence of any difference between right and wrong. That is the
‘standard of abstract right and wrong’ that is apparently taught in the
American home. And it is perfectly obvious, on the face of it, that it is not a
standard of abstract right or wrong at all”. In continuation, Gilbert Keith
gives his particular definition of these American standards: “It is a chaos
of social and sentimental accidents and associations, some of them snobbish,
all of them provincial, but, above all, nearly all of them concrete and
connected with a materialistic prejudice against particular materials”.
There’s also a new reference to Miss Carlson that helps him to criticise the “American
Culture, in the decay of Puritanism” –remarks on standards and ideals-: “And
yet the writer in question calmly proposes that we should abolish all ideas of
right and wrong, and abandon the whole human conception of a standard of
abstract justice, because a boy in Boston cannot be induced to think that a
nice girl is a devil when she smokes a cigarette”; let’s stop up to here
for emphasising the weight a polemic issue like smoking has and, why not,
mentioning this theme has continued to be cause troubles till nowadays.
Therefore, we could extract this author was also worried about the surrounding
environment and he doesn’t doubt a moment to declare his feelings. “If the
rising generation were faced with no worse doubts and difficulties than this,
it would not be very difficult to reconcile them to the traditions of truth and
justice. But I think the episode is worth mentioning, merely because it throws
a ray of light on the moral condition of American Culture, in the decay of
Puritanism. And when next we are told that the idealism of America is to set a
‘standard’ by which England must transform herself, it will be well to remember
what is apparently meant by a standard and an ideal”.
Still without
leaving the main point of considering what is right or either wrong, Chesterton
is talking now of the offspring, despite he doesn’t mind the matter in the
slightest: “Prohibition is sometimes praised for its simplicity. But I
myself do not say anything so absurd as that Americans are savages; nor do I
think it would matter much if they were descended from savages. It is culture
that counts and not ethnology; and the culture that is concerned here derives
indirectly rather from New England that from Old America. Whatever it derives
from, however, this is the thing to be noted about it: that it really does not
seem to understand what is meant by a standard of right and wrong”. To
judge by what has been read, this can be considered as one of the most
important thesis defended in this very essay.
G.K. also
addresses Miss Carlson, telling her Puritan people in America don’t have much
of morality. He speaks to her as a manner of hint, as follows: “I would
therefore venture to say to Miss Avis Carlson that the quarrel in question does
not arise from the Yankee Puritans having too much morality, but from their
having too little. It does not arise from their drawing too hard and fast a
line of distinction between right and wrong, but from their being much to loose
and indistinct (...) I hope at least that some of the Fundamentalists will
succeed in being a little more fundamental than this”. Before sentencing
the writing in question, our man of letters institutes a comparison between “the
old secret society” and “the new secret” one. Thus, he redacts: “The
old secret society may have been justified or not; but it had a definite
object: it was directed against somebody. The new secret society seems to have
been directed against somebody; often against anybody who drank; in time, for
all I know, against anybody who smoked”. Finally, he concludes: “It is
this sort of formless fanaticism that is the great danger of the American
Temperament; and it is well to insist that if men must persecute, they will be
more clear-headed if they persecute for a creed”. As a consequence of all
this, one must have clear that men ought to follow something they believe in,
and they mustn’t be influenced themselves by their fanaticism.
As far as
philosophy itself concerns in the essay above, we should match this with the
following one, with the title of “On Mending and Ending Things”, that
came out on December the 23rd, 1905, in Illustrated London News, and
whose chief claiming is the importance of understanding a things nature or,
what is the same, catching the truth of a concept who happens to be a timeless truth. So, it’s exposed to us
through the explanation of the difference between MENDING and ENDING, which
seem to be alike terms but they are contrary to each other: “’It must be
mended or ended’. Few people who use this useful phrase about reform notice the
important thing about it. The important thing about it is that the two methods
described here are not similar but opposite; between mending and ending that is
not a difference of degree but of vital antagonism of kind. ‘Mending’ is based
upon the idea that the original nature of a thing is good; ‘ending’ is based upon
the idea that the original nature of a thing is bad or, at least, has lost all
power of being good (...) a thing is either bad or good in its original aims
and functions. If it is good, we are in favour of mending it; and because we
are in favour of mending it, we are necessarily opposed to ending it. If it is
bad, we are in favour of ending it; and because we are in favour of ending it,
we ought to fly into a passion at the mere thought of mending it”.
As a way of explaining
this opposition, Chesterton recurs to the ideal philosophy: “(...) there is
nothing so really practical and urgent as ideal philosophy”. And, after
that, we are shown a thesis about this sort of philosophy: “It is a
practical course to destroy a thing; but the only other practical course is to
idealise it”.
Forthwith, it
would not be bed to have a track the short article called “Philosophy for
the Schoolroom” (Daily News, June 22, 1907) for going on with this writer’s
particular philosophy. Here we come across a brief listing of the necessary
beliefs for free thought; the same Gilbert advertises the philosophy or, as he
brands it, “The Alphabet of Thinking”, as an abstract thing which can be
developed in a school, in a common schoolroom with a blackboard, etc. (for
example, arguments, dogmas,...). Then, we can allude to some of his lines
appearing in this case: “Every argument begins with an infallible dogma, and
that infallible dogma can only be disputed by falling back on some other
infallible dogmas; you can never prove your first statement or it would not be
your first. All this is the alphabet of thinking. And it has this special and
positive point about it, that it can be taught in a school, like the other
alphabet. Not to start an argument without stating your postulates could be
taught in philosophy as it is taught in Euclid, in a common schoolroom with a
blackboard”. And, once again, Chesterton’s faith comes up: “Much of our
chaos about religion and doubt arises from this –that our modern sceptics
always begin by telling us what they do not believe. But even in a sceptic we
want to know what he does believe. Before arguing, we want to know what we need
not argue about. And this confusion is infinitely increased by the fact that
all the sceptics of our time are sceptics at different degrees of the
dissolution of scepticism. Now you and I have, I hope, this advantage over all
those clever new philosophers, that we happen not to be mad”. In addition,
I would dare to remark the relationship with the scepticism and the “new
philosophers”: our writer has already complaint about sceptic people –let’s
remember his essay “The Extraordinary Cabman”- and now he makes a speech about
them with the usual irony which characterises his attitude towards all of them.
Another of the
conclusions we might take from this composition is the point that mankind
believes in plenty of things that can’t be justified or proved –G.K. makes a
listing of the necessary beliefs for free thought: “But let us clearly
realise this fact, that we do believe in a number of things which are part of
our existence, but which cannot be demonstrated. Leave religion for the moment
wholly put of question. All which are unproved and unprovable. Let us state
them roughly. (1) Every sane man believes that the world around him and the
people in it are real, and not his own delusion or dream (...) That anything
exists except myself is unproved and unprovable. (2) All sane men believe that this
world not only exists, but matters. Every man believes there is a sort of
obligation on us to interest ourselves in this vision or panorama of life (...)
(3) All sane men believe that there is such a thing as a self, or ego, which is
continuous (...) That there is such a paramount “I” is unproved and unprovable.
But it is more than unproved and unprovable; it is definitely disputed by many
metaphysicians. (4) Lastly, most sane men believe, and all sane men in practice
assume, that they have a power of choice and responsibility for action (...)
And if the youth of the future must not (at present) be taught any religion, it
might at least be taught, clearly and firmly, the three or four sanities and
certainties of human free thought”.
To pursue with
the investigation about this English author, let’s change into a distinct
subject, this time involved in the essay whose name is “The Nightmare”;
the dealing of the text is how nightmares are fun, when they are not real, and
therefore we have: “(...) there is nothing so delightful as a nightmare
–when you know it is a nightmare. That is the essential. That is the stern
condition laid upon all artists touching this luxury of fear. The terror must
be fundamentally frivolous. Sanity may play with insanity; but insanity must
not be allowed to play with sanity (here there’s an obvious literary pun
which is used by Chesterton to dwell on the main point and, apart from that,
making the writing be faster). Let such poets as the one I was reading in
the garden, by all means, be free to imagine what outrageous deities and
violent landscapes they like. By all means, let them wander freely amid their
opium pinnacles and perspectives. But these huge gods, these high cities, are
toys (what we find now is a kind of metaphor, another literary resort);
they must never for an instant be allowed to be anything else. Man, a gigantic
child, must play with Babylon and Nineveh, with Isis and with Ashtaroth. By all
means, let him take up the Burden of Tyre, so long as he can take it lightly.
But the old gods must be his dolls, not his idols. His central sanctities, his
true possessions, should be Christian and simple”. To complete what has
been said, our author resorts to philosophical tones again, although with a
farther meaning: “Now in sober truth there is a magnificent idea in these
monsters of the Apocalypse. It is, I suppose, the idea that beings really more
beautiful or more universal than we are might appear to us frightful and even
confused”.
Reassuming the
previous statements, Gilbert expresses that “I like monsters beneath the
throne very much. It is when one of them goes wandering in deserts and finds a
throne for himself that evil faiths begin, and there is (literally) the devil
to pay in dancing girls or human sacrifice. As long as those misshapen
elemental powers are around the throne, remember that the thing that they
worship is the likeness of the appearance of a man. That is, I fancy, the true
doctrine on the subject of Tales of Terror and such things, which unless a man
of letters do well and truly believe, without doubt he will end by blowing his
brains out or by writing badly”. Inserting a new comment on philosophy
about men, he adds: “Man, the central pillar of the world must be upright
and straight; around him all the trees and beasts and elements and devils may
crook and curl like smoke if they choose”. And, at the end, it’s
highlighting this observation: “All really imaginative literature is only
the contrast between the weird curves of Nature and the straightness of the
soul”, in which oneself can denote the rule the literary genre plays on
this essay. To cut away with it, Chesterton clarifies: “(...) I see no wrong
in riding with the Nightmare tonight (...) We will rise to that mad infinite
where there is neither up nor down, the high topsy-turveydom of the heavens. I
will ride on the Nightmare; but she shall not ride on me”.
One of the
aspects, out of the last commented essay, in which G.K. was equally radical is
the Medievalism, and this caused him to write and remember the forgotten
virtues of the Middle Ages in “On Turnpikes and Medievalism”, which
happened to become a newspaper column, later collected in his book “All I
survey” (1933). It begins with a parallelism between the Middle Ages and modern
times, a point often analysed by him too (we’d better rename “A Defence of Rash
Vows”), in order to compare with past times: “Opening my newspaper the other
day, I saw a short but emphatic leaderette entitled ‘A Relic of Medievalism’.
It expressed a profound indignation upon the fact that somewhere or other, in
some fairly remote corner of this country, there is a turnpike-gate, with a
toll. It insisted that this antiquated tyranny is insupportable, because it is
supremely important that our road traffic should go very fast; presumably a
little faster than it does. So it described the momentary delay in this place
as a relic of medievalism. I fear the future will look at that sentence,
somewhat sadly and a little contemptuously, as a very typical relic of modernism.
I mean it will be a melancholy relic of the only period in all human history
when people were proud of being modern. For though today is always today and
the moment is always modern, we are the only men in all history who fell back
upon bragging about the mere fact that today is not yesterday. I fear that some
in the future will explain it by saying that we had precious little else to
brag about. For, whatever the medieval faults, they went with one merit.
Medieval people never worried about being medieval; and modern people do worry
horribly about being modern”. In the same way, Chesterton demonstrates the
Medieval times’ influence on modern times: “The modern world contains a good
many relics of medievalism” (he puts, as some examples, the Webminster Abbey,
Dante’s Divine Comedy and Chaucer’s Canterbury Tales).Thus, theauthor reaches a
point of even hating the cult of
progress.
A mention apart
is deserved by the following work. I’m referring to “The Case for the
Ephemeral”, excerpted from “All Things Considered”, an e-text in progress
from an edition by John Lane Company, New York, 1909. The essential point here
is the defence of transitory things; to start with it, G.K. Chesterton
criticises his entire book (“All Things Considered”) for being too long –due to
he was in a hurry, according to him, while he was writing it-. Personally, I
think the first words are principally sincere and revealing: “I cannot
understand the people who take literature seriously; but I can love them, and I
do. Out of my love I warn them to keep clear of this book. It is a collection
of crude and shapeless papers upon current or rather flying subjects”;
because of what he says, fashionable issues worry him and literature seems to
be more or less useless, but in fact it turns out to be his passion. Going on
with this, he retakes the critic this way: “Their chief vice is that so many
of them are very serious; because I had no time to make them flippant. It is so
easy to be solemn; it is so hard to be frivolous”. Now he complaints the
book has much of soberness, what may look like a bit incomprehensible, but
anyway, his intention continues to clarify the context through the union to the
responsibility: “Responsibility, a heavy and cautious responsibility of
speech, is the easiest thing in the world; anybody can do it”. Perhaps if
we stop to make a reflection about that, then we’ll be able to realise its
truth: he immerses himself into the politic world (“That is why so many
tired, elderly, and wealthy men go in for politics. They are responsible,
because they have not the strength of mind left to be irresponsible”), a
difficult and troubling matter if we take into account the rough situation at
his time –the beginning of the 20th century-, when everything was
developing towards further improvements and his will was utterly not in favour
of it, provided that his preference presumed to be Medieval stuff.
“I resume the
defence of this indefensible book. These articles have another disadvantage
arising from the scurry in which they were written; they are too long-winded
and elaborate. One of the great disadvantages of hurry is that it takes such a
long time”,
he declares. Note that he uses rather a clash more proximate to a rhetoric
paradox than to anything else. “I feel frightfully annoyed with myself for
not getting to the point more quickly; but I had not enough leisure to be
quick”.
In the same
argument, he stresses the disliking of modernism and gathers his personal
fight, nay outcry, versus modernism: “(...) these pages contain a sort of
protest against the boast of certain writers that they are merely recent. They
brag that their philosophy of the universe or the new philosophy, or the
advanced and progressive philosophy –let’s emphasise his intention to
manifest the clear transience of inventions and progresses, which he tries to
beat by means of the tradition-. I have said much against a mere modernism
(...) I am conscious of a general irritation expressed against the people who
boast of their advancement and modernity in the discussion of religion. But I
never succeeded in saying the quite clear and obvious thing that is really the
matter with modernism. The real objection to modernism is simply that it is a
form of snobbishness”. Newly, he penetrates into the sphere of the
religion, and that’s why I dare to say this author is really obsessed with
these both aspects: modernity and faith, making his texts become a mite
monotone. The term pronounced by him as a “religious persecution” gains
the leading role at this moment: “The pure modernist is merely a snob; he
cannot bear to be a month behind the fashion. Similarly I find that I have
tried in these pages to express the real objection to philanthropists and have
not succeeded (the own Chesterton feels he has failed; from a global
outlook, we could conclude he has got a patent pessimistic mind, as he proves
the surrounding society does not fit him or, better said, he has not settled
down in the contemporary environment). I have not seen the quite simple
objection to the causes advocated by certain wealthy idealists; causes of which
the cause called teetotalism is the strongest case. I have used many abusive
terms about the thing, calling it Puritanism, or superciliousness, or aristocracy;
but I have not seen and stated the quite simple objection to philanthropy;
which is that it is religious persecution (...) the essence of religious
persecution is this: that the man who happens to have material power in the
State, either by wealth or by official position, should govern his
fellow-citizens not according to their religion or philosophy, but according to
his own”.
Next, it should
be strongly recommended to look at the plainness with what Gilbert Keith shows
a case as an instance for his defended reasons: he refers to vegetarianism (we
might find a commonplace with his essay “Asparagus”, already commented) and
teetotalism, and he also carries out a comparison between the two of them: “There
is a very strong case for vegetarianism as compared with teetotalism. Drinking
one glass of beer cannot by any philosophy be drunkenness; but killing one
animal can, by this philosophy, be murder. The objection to both processes is
not that they two creeds, teetotal and vegetarian, are not admissible; it is
simply that they are not admitted. The thing is religious persecution because
it is not based on the existing religion of the democracy”. So far, the
writer demonstrates his widespread capacity as far as religious knowledge
concerns –he establishes a complex relation from one, religious persecution, to
the other, religion of the democracy. What immediately follows that is another
example, this time attached to his rejection towards “the Tory attempt”:
“I was against the Tory attempt to force upon ordinary Englishmen a Catholic
theology in which they do not believe. I am even more against the attempt to
force upon them a Mohamedan morality which they actively deny”.
Partly,
Chesterton talks of his close society again, chaining it to his own profession,
journalism, and his way or method of writing (more personal, what induces us to
regard it as a honest monologue: “Again, in the case of anonymous journalism
I seem to have said a great deal without getting out the point very clearly.
Anonymous journalism is dangerous, and is poisonous in our existing life simply
because it is so rapidly becoming an anonymous life. That is the horrible thing
about our contemporary atmosphere. Society is becoming a secret society”.
As a consequence of his costume to go back to the same thing once and another,
he returns to the point of responsibility, the writers and their conduct
–however, he focuses his glance now at other ones-, informing about how their
behaviour should be: “The rich publisher may treat the poor poet better or
worse than the old master workman treated the old apprentice. But the
apprentice ran away and the master ran after him. Nowadays it is the poet who
pursues and tries in vain to fix the fact of responsibility. It is the
publisher who runs away”. Before leaving this article, let’s pay attention
to the resort of showing parallelisms and comparisons constantly: rich
publisher-poor poet, old master workman-apprentice, like religious
persecution-religion of the democracy.
In the last
analysis, why not alluding the conclusion? It contains a new quotation about
responsibility and a note referring to our attitude to the same writers: “The
elaborate machinery which was once used to make men responsible is now used
solely in order to shift the responsibility. People talk about the pride of
tyrants; but we in this age are not suffering from the pride of tyrants. We are
suffering from the shyness of tyrants (...) Therefore we must not encourage
leader-writers to be shy (...) Rather we must attempt to lure them to be vain
and ostentatious; so that through ostentation they may al last find their way
to honesty”. Eventually, this manner of concluding also consists of a last
damnation to “All Things Considered”: “The last indictment against this book
is the worst of all. It is simply this: that if all goes well, this book will
be unintelligible gibberish (...) Brief as is the career of such a book as
this, it may last just twenty minutes longer than most of the philosophies that
it attacks. In the end, it will not matter to us whether we wrote well or ill;
whether we fought with flails or reeds. I will matter to us greatly on which
side we fought”.
If, whoever the
reader is, he/she thinks Gilbert Keith Chesterton is an antiquated author,
permit me tell him/her he/she is wrong. Otherwise, you only have to look upon a
posterior essay, “The Great Shipwreck as Analogy” by name, written on
May the 11th, 1912, after the Titanic sunk. It was first found in
The Illustrated London News.
As the title
says, there’s an analogy “between the great modern ship and our great modern
society”. Gilbert attacks our civilisation, comparing it to the Titanic and
its feebleness or, what is more, its lack of safety. Thus, he aims: “The
tragedy of the great shipwreck is too terrific for any analogies of mere fancy.
It is a fact; a fact perhaps too large and plain for the eyes easily to take
in. Our whole civilisation is indeed very like the TITANIC; alike in its power
and its impotence, its insecurity”. Along this essay, we can imagine we are
psychologists and investigate human minds, for we are shown the fact such a
fantastic and luxury vessel makes one be more careless and this is really
dangerous: “By the time you have made your ship as big as a commonwealth, it
does become very like a ship –rather like a sinking ship. For there is a real
connection between such catastrophes and a certain frame of mind which refuses
to expect them (...) But if you make your boat so large that it does not even
look like a boat, but like a sort of watering-place, it must, by the deepest
habit of human nature, induce a less vigilant attitude of the mind”. In the
same line of reflection, there are some philosophical (if we want to modify it,
we’d better say ‘psychological’) remarks: “The mental process is quite
illogical, but it is quite inevitable. Of course, both sailors and passengers
are intellectually aware that motors at sea are often less useful than
life-boats, and that ices are no antidote to icebergs. But man is not only
governed by what he thinks but by what he chooses to think about; and the
sights that sink into us day by day colour our minds with every tint between
insolence and terror. This is one of the worst evils in that extreme separation
of social classes which marks the modern ship –and State (we may understand
the meaning of this by glancing backwards at the title again: there’s an
obvious analogy between the social discrimination in the huge Titanic as well
as in the own State). Moreover, we distinguish a continuation with what has
been told, at the beginning, about modernity, and a determinate relationship
with reality and unreality: “But whether or no our unhappy fellow-creatures
on the Titanic suffered more than they need from this unreality of original
outlook, they cannot have had less instinct of actuality than we have who are
left alive on land: and now that they are much more real than we” (he is
pessimistic about the panorama but maybe optimistic and more profound regarding
to those who lost their lives in that far-for-us disaster). There’s a certain
kind of mystery round the dead in the catastrophe. As an example, the case of
Sylvia Pankhurst: “It is this curious, cold, flimsy incapacity to conceive
what a THING is like that appears in so many places, even in the comments on
this astounding sorrow. It appears in the displeasing incident of Miss Sylvia
Pankhurst, who, immediately after the disaster, seems to have hastened to
assure the public that men must get no credit for giving the boats up to women,
because it was the ‘rule’ al sea”. The deduction of him about it are these:
“It is vain to rule if your subjects can and do disobey you. It is vain to
vote if your delegates can and do disobey you (...) And if the word ‘rule’ be
used in the wider sense of an attempt to maintain a certain standard of private
conduct out of respect for public opinion, we can only say that not only is
this a real moral triumph –remarking at present the term ‘moral’ and all it
involves if we go back some of his previous articles, such as “Negative and
Positive Morality”-, but it is, in our present condition, rather a
surprising and reasurring one. It is exactly this corporate conscience that the
modern State has dangerously neglected”.
At last, we are
talked of the acquaintances of people on board: “There was probably more
instinctive fraternity and sense of identical interests, I will say, not on an
old skipper’s vessel, but on an old pirate’s, than there was between the
emigrants, the aristocrats, the journalists, or the millionaires who set out to
die together on the great ship. That they found in so cruel a way their
brotherhood and the need of man for the respect of his neighbour, this is a
dreadful fact, but certainly the reverse of a degrading one”.
As he did with
Sylvia Pankhurst, Chesterton names here the case of a man called Mr Stead, and
he configures another example of the great shipwreck –even this bloke could be
considered as somehow praised by the essayist-: “The case of Mr Stead, which
I feel with rather special emotions, both of sympathy and difference, is very
typical of the whole tragedy. Mr Stead was far too great and brave a man to
require any concealment of his exaggerations or his more unbalanced moods; his
strength was in a flaming certainty, which one only weakens by calling
sincerity, and a hunger and thirst for human sympathy. His excess, we may say,
with real respect, was in the direction of megalomania; a childlike belief in
big empires, big newspapers, big alliances –big ships (this last comment
has more of a critic than worship). He toiled like a Titan for that
Anglo-American combination of which the ship that has gone down may well be
called the emblem. And at the last all these big things broke about him, and
somewhat bigger things remained: a courage that was entirely individual; a
kindness that was entirely universal. His death may become a legend –as,
indeed, occurred with the sunk of the Titanic”.
Passing now to
other matters, we could analyse Gilbert’s essay “The Suffragist”, in
which we find out his political point of view, related to women. To take an obvious example, he makes an introduction
explaining that political womanhood called ‘Suffragettes’ is a term often
confused: “Like most other popular sentiments, it is generally wrongly
stated even when it is rightly felt (...) For the things which are the simplest
so long as they are undisputed invariably become the subtlest when once they
are disputed”. This reports lead, next, to a description of the opposition
between sexes stating as follows: “And this matter of the functions of the
sexes is primarily a matter of the instincts; sex and breathing are about the
only two things that generally work best when they are least worried about.
That, I suppose, is why the same sophisticated age that has poisoned the world
with Feminism is also polluting it with Breathing Exercises. We plunge at once
into a forest of false analogies and bad blundering history; while almost any
man or woman left to themselves would know at least that sex is quite different
from anything else in the world –here it can be commented the magnitude the
essayist deals with in this subject, which has been, moreover, a very
controversial affair since the ancient times-. There is no kind of
comparison possible between a quarrel of a man and woman (however right the
woman may be) and the other quarrels of slave and master, of rich and poor, or
of patriot and invader, with which the Suffragists deluge us every day”. Lately,
he compares the dichotomy man-woman with other cases of transcendent
controversy like those quoted. But what excels is the way he talks about
responsible females, simply saying that “Real responsible woman has never
been silly”, what can induce us to understand a certain point of irony,
though true at once, in the statement.
Proceeding with
this narration, it’s extremely important the assertion that exposes that “(...)
the very first fact about sexes is that they like each other”. Maybe this
chances to clear this scheme up: “The sexes cannot wish to abolish each
other; and, if we allow them any sort of permanent opposition, it will sink
into something as base as a party system (let’s also notice his aversion
against political disposition in general). As marriage, therefore, is rooted
in an aboriginal unity of instincts, you cannot compare it, even in its
quarrels, with any of the mere collisions of separate institutions”. It’s
overseen, then, how sexes and instincts are joined together; and this will be
the chief view globally: to prove that the attraction of the sexes is the most
fundamental issue, he declares: “(...) any philosophy about the sexes that
begins with anything but the mutual attraction of the sexes, begins with a
fallacy; and all its historical comparisons are as irrelevant and impertinent
as puns”. And said that, it’s attached to the instincts anew: “But to
expose such cold negation of the instincts is easy: to express or even half
express the instincts is very hard (...) They are much concerned with how a
thing is done, as well as whether one may do it: and the deepest elements in
their attraction or aversion can often only be conveyed by stray examples or
sudden images”.
Chesterton
plays with words, not taking notice of what he has said about impertinent puns
before: “The point is not that women are unworthy of votes; it is not even
that votes are unworthy of men, so long as they are merely votes; and have
nothing in them of this ancient militarism of democracy”. Reading that “No
honest man dislikes the public woman. He can only dislike the political woman;
an entirely different thing”, one can acquire the knowledge of his attack
to female politicians, something he is making obvious once and another. For
finishing with it, he draws the conclusion now transcribed: “I only write
here of the facts of natural history; and the fact is that it is this, and not
the publicity or importance, that hurts. It is for the modern world to judge
whether such instincts are indeed danger signals; and whether the hurting of
moral as of material nerves is a tocsin and a warning of nature”. His
obsession about modern society and morality is patent at the end, aside his
desire of avoiding the polemic and let the moderns opine about his defences.
But before
leaving the subject of differentiation of sexes, why not having a look at “The
Equality of Sexlessness”? There the discrimination is perfectly identified
and we might find an analogy with the previous commented article if we pay
attention to the first words: “In almost all the modern opinions of women it
is curious to observe how many lies have to be assumed before a case can be
made”. At the same time, it makes one denote a new critic to modernity and
women in general, referring to their opinions, which are impregnated with
fallacies. As usual in the author, we are brought to glance at the past, seeing
that “(...) women were (...) enslaved by the convention of natural
inferiority to man”, and Chesterton adds somebody’s observation: “Those
days, we are told, ‘in which women were held incapable of positive social
achievements are gone forever”. Consequently, “The same critic goes on
to state, with all the solemn emphasis of profound thought, that ‘the important
thing is not that women are the same as men –that is fallacy- but that they are
just as valuable to society as men. Equality of citizenship means that there
were twice as many heads to solve present-day problems as there were to solve
the problems of the past. And two heads are better than one”. Gilbert Keith
reassumes his characteristic criticism regarding to the modern times and he
straightens himself and considers the matter in the earnest manner: “And the
dreadful proof of the modern collapse of all that was meant by man and wife and
the family council, is that this sort of imbecility can be taken seriously”.
In order to
explain the principal aim in the essay, i.e., the equality of sexlessness, he
alludes to a point which first appeared in “The London Times”: “The London
Times, in a studied leading article, points out that the first emancipators of
women (whoever they were) had no idea what lay in store for future generations:
‘Could they have foreseen it they might have disarmed much opposition by
pointing to the possibilities, not only of freedom, but of equality and
fraternity also’. And we ask, what does it all mean? What in the name of all
that is graceful and dignified does fraternity with women mean? What nonsense,
or worse, is indicated by the freedom and equality of the sexes? We mean something
quite definite when we speak of a man being a little free with the ladies. What
definite freedom is meant when the freedom of women is proposed? (important
to notice the ramblings the writer composes for reaching the answer: that
provides, beyond all doubt, a fast pace to the text and helps to emphasise it.
However, it also involves calling the reader’s attendance) (...) If it
means, as we fear it does, freedom from responsibility of managing a home and a
family, an equal right with men in business and social careers, at the expense
of home and family, then such progress we can only call progressive
deterioration”. He defends, thus, his own thoughts against the evolutions
the improvements carry out.
Finally, we are
taught equality and fraternity are expected with the establishment of
sexlessness: “And for men too, there is, according to a famous authoress, a
hope of freedom. Men are beginning to revolt, we are told, against the old
tribal custom of desiring fatherhood. The male is casting off the shackles of
being a creator and a man. When all are sexless there will be but fraternity,
free and equal. The only consoling thought is that it will endure but for one
generation”. This essay is an extract from GK’s Weekly, July 26, 1930.
The article “Government
and the Rights of Man” –written on July the 30th, 1921 for
Illustrated London News- is in the same tendency of politics, but it is treated with a further grasp: the writer
sets out the theme of freedom and begins to make a speech of how words hurt
people: “I could never see why a man who is not free to open his mouth to
drink should be free to open it to talk. Talking does far more direct harm to
other people (...) it is certain that a vast amount of evil would be prevented
if we all wore gags”. Moreover, he deepens in the subject of liberty and
explains the possible solutions to the problem: “The answer is that, unless
a man is allowed to talk, he might as well be a chimpanzee who is only able to
chatter. In other words, if a man loses the responsibility for these
rudimentary functions and forms of freedom, he loses not only his citizenship,
but his manhood. But there are other personal liberties still permitted to us,
more elaborate and civilised than that simple human speech which is still
closely akin to the chatter of the chimpanzees”.
Then,
separately but in addition to what he pronounces for clearing it up, we are
introduced a parable of a Post Office in order to talk about the rights of
mankind that are to be left by the same government: “By some oversight,
which I am quite unable to explain, we are still allowed to write private
letters if we put them in public pillar-boxes (...) And all this anarchy and
deterioration could be stopped by the simple process of standardisation of all
correspondence”. Thus, he alludes to Mr H.G. Wells, a sceptic criticised by
him very often (like G.B. Shaw; let’s recall his essay “The Extraordinary
Cabman”) and makes nomenclature once more of the social reform, which gathers
some other remarks of him about Socialism: “I know if I use the word
‘standardisation’, Mr H.G. Wells will welcome it and begin to think of it
seriously [indeed there opens before me a vista of vast social reform]”.
And then what happens is that he shows his contempt for correspondence
-something clear if we take refuge in his proclaim at the parable-: ”I very
seldom write to anybody; and I never write to the people I like best. About
them I do not trouble, for they understand. But there are unanswered letters
from total strangers about which I feel a remorse”.
Partly referring to the previous comments
about answering all the people he would have killed and even leaving them some
money when he died, he makes a contrast telling as follows: “(...) I am not
really converted to my own project, even by my own failure. I am not really
convinced of the necessity of standardised correspondence, either by the
existence of criminal letters or my own criminal neglect of letters”. And,
subsequently, there’s a critic to modern talk: “If or when, in some strange
mood at some distant date, I should actually answer a letter, I should still
prefer to answer it myself. Even if I had nothing to write except an apology
for not writing, I should prefer my self-abasement to have the character of
self-determination. It is a most extraordinary fact that all modern talk about
self-determination is applied to everything except the self”. This precedes
the conclusion at the end, in which we are explained the clear purpose of the
quoted composition: “(...) the question I have here discussed under the
parable of the Post Office is not the question of whether there are abuses in
drink or diet, as there are calumny and blackmail in any pillar-box or
postman’s bag. It is the question of whether in these days the claims of
government are to leave anything whatever of the rights of man”.
As a proof of how fundamental liberty is
for Gilbert Keith, why not looking now at “The Free Man”? There we find
the mentioned topic chained to religions already in the initial paragraph: “The idea of liberty has
ultimately a religious root; that is why men find it so easy to die for and so
difficult to define. It refers finally to the fact that, while the oyster and
the palm tree have to save their lives by law, man has to save his soul by
choice”. If we are able to denote a certain trace of morality, maybe we
should base on the following statement: “Generally, the moral substance of
liberty is this: that man is not meant merely to receive good laws, good food:
or good conditions, like a tree in a garden, but is meant to take a certain
princely pleasure in selecting and shaping like the gardener (a new
reference to this profession)”. If we move forward, we read that “Perhaps
that is the meaning of the trade of Adam”: the instance of Adam, like in
“The Gardener and the Guinea”, shows a little bit of his sensibility round
religion and it’s repeated, but with relationship to God and the Creation,
presenting the man as a creator: “And the best popular words for rendering
the real idea of liberty are those which speak of man as a creator. We use the
word ‘make’ about most of the things in which freedom is essential, as a
country walk or a friendship or a love affair. When a man ‘makes his way’
through a wood he has really created, he has built a road, like the Romans.
When a man ‘makes a friend’, he makes a man. And in the third case we talk of a
man ‘making love’, as if he were (as, indeed, he is) creating new masses and
colours of that flaming material and awful form of manufacture”.
But Chesterton
does not conform with pointing out to freedom simply in the way above, and then
he analyses it from a deeper outlook, which is not another but the liberty in
two senses: spiritual and political: “In its primary spiritual sense,
liberty is the god in man, or, if you like the word, the artist. In its
secondary political sense, liberty is the living influence of the citizen on
the State in the direction of moulding or deflecting it”. In fact, human
beings are the unique who disposes of liberty: “Men are the only creatures
that evidently possess it. On the other hand, the eagle has no liberty; he only
has loneliness. On the other hand, ants, bees, and beavers exhibit the highest
miracle of the State influencing the citizen; but no perceptible trace of the
citizen influencing the State”.
Religiosity
tuns out to go on constituting the first interest for the author, so he tries
to draw the relationship between humanity and it: “(...) The isolation of
this idea in humanity is humanity akin to its religious character; but it is
not even in humanity by any means equally distributed. The idea that the State
should not only be supported by its children (...) but should be constantly
criticised and reconstructed by them, is an idea stronger in Christendom than
any other part of the planet; stronger in Western than Eastern Europe”. And
finally, resorting to politics, he manages to declare that “(...) touching
the pure idea of the individual being free to speak and act within limits, the
assertion of this idea, we may fairly say, has been the peculiar honour own
country (...) And there was a real old English sincerity in the vulgar chorus
that ‘Britons never shall be slaves’. We had no equality and hardly any
justice; but freedom we were really fond of. And I think just now it is worth
while to draw attention to the old optimistic prophecy that ‘Britons never
shall be slaves’. The mere love of liberty has never been at a lower ebb in
England than it has been for the last twenty years (...) Two hundred years ago
we turned out the Stuarts rather than endanger the Habeas Corpus Act. Two years
ago we abolished the Habeas Corpus Act rather than turn out the Home Secretary.
We passed a law (which is now in force) that an Englishman’s punishment shall
not depend upon judge and jury, but upon the governors and jailers who have got
hold of him (...) // Political liberty (...) consists in the power of
criticising those flexible parts of the State which constantly require
reconsideration, not the basis, but the machinery. In plainer words, it means
the power of saying the sort of things that a decent but discontented citizen
wants to say (...) // the forbidding of (...) things (whether just or not) is
only tyranny in a secondary and special sense. It restrains the abnormal, not
the normal man. But the normal man, the decent discontented citizen, does want
to protest against unfair law courts (...) If he is run in for doing this (as
he will be) he does want to proclaim the character or known prejudices of the
magistrate who tries him. If he is sent to prison (as he will be) he does want
to have clear and civilised sentence, telling him when he will come out. And
these are literally and exactly the things that he now cannot get. That is the
almost cloying humour of the present situation”. As we can see, Chesterton
is extremely concerned about the current matters and spares no effort to make
it public. And the current worrying for him is the fact that one is not able to
proclaim openly his/her feelings merely because it may cause disturbances in
the environmental society.
As a way of
closing this article, he admits “I can say abnormal things in modern
magazines. It is the normal things that I am not allowed to say (...) The thing
I must not write is rational criticism of the men and institutions of my
country. The present condition of England is briefly this: That no Englishman
can say in public a twentieth part of what he says in private”. The proof
of how true what he says is: “One cannot say, for instance, that –But I am
afraid I must leave out that instance, because one cannot say it. I cannot
prove my case- because it is so true”.
If we take a
look at the composition “The Sectarian of Society”, we’ll see another
linking to freedom; so then, Chesterton defends liberty in the surroundings
and, therefore, there must exist credo, as he says: “A fixed creed is absolutely
indispensable to freedom”. As a matter of fact, this involves communication
through the wit and the essayist justifies that by confessing: “For while
men are and should be various, there must be some communication between them if
they are to get any pleasure out of their variety. And an intellectual formula
is the only thing that can create a communication that does not depend on mere
blood, class, or capricious sympathy”. In order to show an instance of
these statements, Gilbert chooses Socialism: “(...) instead of a small and
varied group, you have enormous monotonous groups. Instead of the liberty of
dogma, you have a tyranny of taste. Allegory apart, instances of what I mean
will occur to every one; perhaps the most obvious is Socialism. Socialism means
the ownership by the organ of government (whatever it is) of all things
necessary to production (...) When once it has been discovered that Socialism
does not mean a narrow economic formula, it is also discovered that Socialism
does mean wearing one particular kind of clothes, reading one particular kind
of books, hanging up one particular kind of pictures, and in the majority of
cases even eating one particular kind of food. For men must recognise each
other somehow. These men will not know each other somehow. These men will not
know each other by a principle, like fellow-citizens. They cannot know each
other by a smell, like dogs. So they have to fall back on general colouring”.
Repeatedly, the author resorts to political schemes to entrust his affirmations
to the readers and, what is more, he intends to prevent people from
considering, in this case, the Socialism in a superfluous way such as that of
thinking it to be “a narrow economic formula”, and urges them to resign
themselves to accept this type of government in a more sensitive manner: the
fact of forming a society. And maybe this community constituted by determinate
people causes him to wander through so many different issues in order to set
out the several dilemmas on his time -though,
nevertheless, we generally continue to be surrounded by these difficulties
nowadays: indeed, Chesterton actually seem to predict the future situation-.
In a parallel
way, and for taking another example, our appreciated man of letters turns back
to decant towards the side of religion: “(...) it is supremely so in the
case of religion. As long as you have a creed, which every one in a certain
group believes or is supposed to believe, then that group will consist of the
old recurring figures of religious history, who can be appealed to by the creed
and judged by it; the saint, the hypocrite, the brawler, the weak brother.
These people do each other good; or they all join together to do the hypocrite
good, with heavy and repeated blows. But once break the bond of doctrine which
alone holds these people together, each will gravitate to his own kind outside
the group. The hypocrites will all get together and call each other saints; the
saints will get lost in a desert and call themselves weak brethren; the weak
brethren will get weaker and weaker in a general atmosphere of imbecility; and
the brawler will go off looking for somebody else with whom to brawl. This has
very largely happened to modern English religion”. Like in previous
occasions, modernity and religiosity are matched and, as a result of their
union, criticised by the writer, who is strongly hostile to the current
progress and the situation produced as a consequence of it. “But wherever
the falsity appears, it comes from neglect of the same truth: that men should
agree on a principle, that they may differ on everything else; that God gave
men a law that they might turn it into liberties”. In the same way, we are
taught the line which chains all this entanglement and, generally talking, the
explanation of the essay: the principle all the human beings should follow is
the same Christianity, the faith in the Almighty (which perhaps is led to other
gates by men’s choice).
The main point
for being successful, according to Chesterton, is the opposition of elements: “As
a matter of fact, the more sexes are in violent contrast, the less likely they
are to be in violent collision. The more incompatible their tempers are, the
better”. Let’s stop here to mention the analogy of this text with the one
included in “The Equality of Sexlessness”, where men and women are antagonistic
poles but, contrarily, it implies the welfare state for society. “There are
very few marriages of identical taste and temperament; they are generally
unhappy. But to have the same fundamental theory, to think the same thing a
virtue, whether you practise or neglect it, to think the same thing a sin,
whether you punish or pardon or laugh at it, in the last extremity to call the
same thing duty and the same thing a disgrace –this really is necessary to a
tolerably happy marriage”. Again, this English man leads us to the extent
of the Christian matrimonial sacrament and profits by this point to become
absorbed in the limits of man and woman. “(...) and it is much better
represented by a common religion than it is by affinities and auras. And what
applies to the family applies to the nation. A nation with a root religion will
be tolerant. A nation with no religion will be bigoted”. This gives a good
account of his personal interest in nationalism, as all his essays in which
England appears demonstrate. “(...) Lastly, the worst effect of all is this:
that when men come together to profess a creed, they come courageously (...)
But when they come together in a clique, they come sneakishly, eschewing all
change or disagreement (...)”. Up to this extent, and still getting in
touch with politics, I’d dare to say when a man ‘profess a creed’ and he fails
through the fault of a bad-posed political point or equally a social
problem –which is being defended- badly understood. That is considered by the
author as a Medical Mistake, which does with a remedy
or cure.
At length, we learn
from the conclusion that men of the same kind go together in mass in order to
follow a creed: “For birds of a feather flock together, but birds of the
white feather most of all”. We may be seduced here to taste the raw
intention in the expression ‘birds of the white feather’... Will it mean that
humanity is really coward? It wouldn’t be very strange if we take into
consideration Chesterton’s ill will towards stupidity of men; an obstinacy that
might have something to do with the temper of stingy people, properly
summarised in “The Miser and his friends”, where we come to the extent
of economical theory and the trouble attached to it, e.g., the distributism; firstly, we have an acute
critic to the modern miser, opposed to the old one: “Whenever the unhealthy
man has been on top, he has left a horrible savour that humanity finds still in
its nostrils. Now, in our time, the unhealthy man is on top; but he is not the
man mad on sex, like Nero; or mad on statecraft, like Louis XI; he is simply
the man mad on money. Our tyrant is not the satyr or the torturer; but the
miser. The modern miser has changed much from the miser of legend and anecdote;
but only because he has grown yet more insane. The old miser had some touch of
the human artist about him in so far that he collected gold (...) The modern
idolater of riches is content with far less genuine things. The glitter of
guineas is like the glitter of buttercups, the chink of pelf is like the chime of
bells, compared with the dreary papers and dead calculations which make the
hobby of the modern miser. The modern millionaire loves nothing so lovable as a
coin (...) And as for comfort, the old miser could be comfortable, as many
tramps and savages are, when he was once used to being unclean (...) The round
coins in the miser’s stocking were safe in some sense. The round noughts in the
millionaire’s ledger are safe in no sense; the same fluctuation which excites
him with their increase depresses him with their diminution”. This is, to a
certain extent, believable because rich men are extremely worried about the
figures in their bank account, what contradicts the mean’s liking, for he just
gets conformed with the simple and material coins. “The miser at least
collects coins; his hobby is numismatics. The man who collects noughts collects
nothings”. However, we are shown the clearest way of this confrontation: in
the easiest of all the cases, collecting coins is more useful than just
increasing the number of figures in one’s wealth. Certainly, here we face the
differences in the élite, id est, between rich and filthy rich people: “It
may be admitted that the man amassing millions is a bit of an idiot; but it may
be asked in what sense does he rule the modern world. The answer to this is
very important and rather curious. The evil enigma for us here is not the rich,
but the Very Rich. The distinction is important; because this special problem
is separate from the old general quarrel about rich and poor that runs through
the Bible and all strong books, old and new. The special problem to-day is that
certain powers and privileges have grown so world-wide and unwieldy that they
are out of the power of the moderately rich as well as of the moderately poor.
They are out of the power of everybody except a few millionaires –that is,
misers”. Having reached this point, Chesterton insists on the fact
millionaires are, indeed, stingier than all the rest of the society (divided
now into moderately rich, now into moderately poor). The same writer recognises
he’s not connected with this discrimination of classes: “In the old normal
friction of normal wealth and poverty I am myself on the Radical side”. The
hated modernity, if put in relation to the rich, has this effect on him: “The
merely rich are not rich enough to rule the modern market. The things that
change modern history (...) are getting too big for everybody except the
misers”. He talks about rich and very rich men and we are set out
moderately rich also include good people: “There are two other odd and
rather important things to be said about them. The first is this: that with
this aristocracy we do not have the chance of a lucky variety in types which
belongs to larger and looser aristocracies. The moderately rich include all
kinds of people, even good people (...) But among the Very Rich you will never
find a really generous man, even by accident. They may give their money away,
but they will never give themselves away; they are egoistic, secretive, dry as
old bones. To be smart enough to get all that money you must be dull enough to
want it”.
And already
now, speaking apart about old and modern miser, it goes on: “Lastly, the
most serious point about them is this: that the new miser is flattered for his
meanness and the old one never was. It was never called self-denial in the old
miser that he lived on bones. It is called self-denial in the new millionaire
if he lives on beans”. For getting rid of this attempt then, Chesterton
extracts these lines: “Of the two I have more respect for the old miser,
gnawing bones in an attic: if he was not nearer to God, he was at least a
little nearer to men. His simple life was a little more like the life of the
real poor”. Even though we cut off this article, we must clarify first the
writer lets his opinion go further than he did in other publications and
expresses openly his contempt towards modern mass and reveals which side he is
in. Besides, one can notice anew the tremendous religiousness of this man (as
God is present everywhere).
Yet, once we
have already analysed other matters such as morality, philosophy, religion or
politics, we reach now the affair of reality. Indeed, we can appreciate
Chesterton’s worry about the shortness of reality of his contemporary society in
the brief article named known us “The Real Journalist”, which begins
this way: “Our age, which has boasted of realism will fail chiefly through
lack of reality”. In addition, the essayist puts the emphasis on the
difference between the essence and the appearance of the thing that is carried
out, and reasons that “Never, I fancy, has there been so grave and startling
a divorce between the real way a thing is done and the look of it when it is
done”. And, in this case, the writer picks as an example the newspaper
itself, for journalism is his own profession and he knows it perfectly well: “I
take the nearest and most topical instance to hand a newspaper (...) Seen from
the outside, it seems to come round as automatically as the clock and as
silently as the dawn. Seen from the inside, it gives all its organisers a gasp
of relief every morning to see that it has come out at all”.
And related to
his job we could consider it’s the matter he shelters in “Cheese”;
Gilbert praises the cheese and expresses it’s disregarded generally in European
Literature, as his work “The Neglect of Cheese in European Literature” shows: “Poets
have been mysteriously silent on the subject of cheese (...) Yet it has every
quality which we require in an exalted poetry. It is a short, strong word; it
rhymes to breeze and seas (an essential point); that it is emphatic in sound is
admitted even by the civilisation of the modern cities (...) The substance
itself is imaginative. It is ancient –sometimes in the individual case, always
in the type and custom (...) nor can I imagine why a man should want more than
bread and cheese, if he can get enough of it”. If we look back a little
bit, we come across the fact he also covered the issue of food in
“Asparagus”... why has he chosen another kind of nourishment this time, and
what for? As it has been proved, it has to do with rhymes and sounds, but let’s
not have enough with it; if we continue to read this essay, we reach the theme
about the clash between bad and good habits, that is, mechanical and poetic
communities, in following quotation: “Now, it is just here that true poetic
civilisation differs from that paltry and mechanical civilisation that holds us
all in bondage. Bad customs are universal and rigid, like modern militarism –critic
towards modernity again-. Good customs are universal and varied, like native
chivalry and self-defence. Both the good and the bad civilisation cover us as
with a canopy, and protect us from all that is outside. But a good civilisation
spreads over us freely like a tree, varying and yielding because it is alive. A
bad civilisation stands up and sticks out above us like an umbrella
–artificial, mathematical in shape; not merely universal, but uniform. So it is
with the contrast between the substances that vary and the substances that are
the same wherever they penetrate. By a wise doom of heaven (he highlights
the importance of God’s Kingdom and how the Creator influences on human beings,
though they’re not parishioners), men were commanded to eat cheese, but not
the same cheese”. If we have a look at the last sentence, it’s standing the
adjective ‘same’, which is used by Chesterton because it has been narrated a
journey he made according to his usual lectures and which let him taste some
different and good kinds of cheese in several inns next to the road. After
having gone out of England, he arrives in Babylon and is served some biscuits
there, instead of cheese he had asked for. Referring to the waiter who served
him, he tells so: “He gave me generally to understand that he was only
obeying a custom of Modern Society. I have therefore resolved to raise my
voice, not against the waiter, but against Modern Society, for this huge and
unparalleled modern wrong”. Once more, we are taught the contempt to
modernity from his literary outlook; the Modern World is stood out with
qualifications that are this time scornful (‘huge and unparalleled’). “Cheese”
was published in “Alarms and Discursions” in 1910.
In “The Poet
and the Cheese”, as the title reveals, cheese turns up, laced anew to
poetry. Gilbert Keith describes a landscape which reminds him of a poet called
Wordsworth and his typical rural poems. This place he drops round is called
Stilton, like a famous brand of cheese and, when the author (and main character
of the story all at once) realises there’s no cheese of this class there, he
becomes perplexed and utters the words: “(...) it seemed to me a strange
allegory of England as she is now; this little town that had lost its glory;
and forgotten, so to speak, the meaning of its own name. And I thought it yet
more symbolic because from that old and full and virile life, the great cheese
was gone; and only the beer remained. And even that will be stolen by the
Liberals or adulterated by the Conservatives”. At the time, we can notice a
certain stress of politics and comparison to England, as a sort of critic for
his own country and, consequently, for the party system.
Another story
in the same line, but much further if we glance at the direct meaning, is “The
Enchanted Man”, where this English erudite focuses on a mishap that
happened to him once he went to see a performance of Buckingham Players titled
“Pot Luck”, by Miss Gertrude Robins, at Naphill Theatre. Like in many other occasions,
he takes profit by the opportunity for alluding his compatriots and sending a
message to the reader: “The English are modest people; that is why they are
entirely ruled and run by the few of them that happen to be immodest”. As
he says, he remembers something queer while being at the theatre, and this is
the result of a wired anecdote that had occurred to him in his previous journey
up to there: “I have troubled recollection of having seen a very good play
and made a very bad speech; I have a cloudy recollection of talking to all
sorts of nice people afterwards, but talking to them jerkily and with half a
head, as a man talks when he has one eye on a clock”.
The Christian
worrying is obvious early: “And the truth is that I had one eye on an ancient
and timeless clock, hung uselessly in heaven; whose very name has passed into a
figure for such bemused folly”. His imagination becomes rather madness when
telling that “I began to fancy that I was spirally climbing the Tower of
Babel in a dream”, what reflects, at the same time, his enormous sense of
religiousness –he takes an extract from the Bible-.
Talking about
his own country in ascertainable political terms, for he turns to some words
thrown out by the patriot Mr Joseph Chamberlain: “From the edge of that
abrupt steep I saw something indescribable, which I am now going to describe.
When Mr Joseph Chamberlain delivered his great patriotic speech on the
inferiority of England to the Dutch parts of South Africa, he made use of the
expression ‘the illimitable veldt’. The word ‘veldt’ is Dutch, and the word
‘illimitable’ is Double Dutch (let’s look here at the linguistic pattern).
But the meditative statesman probably meant that the new plains gave him a
sense of largeness and dreariness which he had never found in England. Well, if
he never found it in England, it was because he never looked for it in England.
In England –the author repeats this place-name for heighten the British
strength and charisma he’s proud of- there is an illimitable number of
illimitable veldts. I saw six or seven separate eternities in cresting as many
different hills. One cannot find anything more infinite than a finite horizon,
free and lonely and innocent. The Dutch veldt may be a little more desolate
than Birmingham. But I am sure it is not so desolate as that English hill was,
almost within a cannon-shot of High Wycombe”. On the other hand, the
mysticism is patent when saying: “There was something heathen about its
union of beauty and death; sorrow seemed to glitter, as it does in some of the
great pagan poems. I understood one of the thousand poetical phrases of the
populace, ‘a God-forsaken place’. Yet something was present there; and I could
not yet find the key to my fixed impression. Then suddenly I remembered the right
word. It was an enchanted place”. Let’s make a recollection –like he
quotes- and relate it newly to the previous essay “The Extraordinary Cabman”,
and we’ll understand his way of narrating such fantastic reports.
“There was
never a better place than POT LUCK; for it
a
tale with a point and a tale that might happen any day among English peasants.
There were never better actors than the local Buckingham Players: for they were
acting their own life with just that rise into exaggeration which is the transition
from life to art”. Gilbert refers to the play
itself, the one he has gone to see at the beginning of this narration, and
later on he finishes off with the phrase “(...) we live in an enchanted
land”. In short, he generalises his own case for comprising the whole
society of his time.
The essay I’m
going to deal with at present, apart, is “The Man Who thinks Backwards”;
as Chesterton explains, “The man who thinks backwards is a powerful person
to-day: indeed, if he is not omnipotent, he is at least omnipresent. It is he
who writes nearly all the learned books and articles, especially of the
scientific or skeptical sort”. Thus, we notice some other ramblings from
the author about sceptic people and scientists altogether, two kinds of beings
he has already grumbled of in different compositions.
We have been
exposed the definition of a man who thinks this way, but: what ‘thinking
backwards’ consists of? He sets it out too: “But especially it is this
strange and tortuous being who does most of the writing about female
emancipation and the reconsidering of marriage (certainly, these are two of
the subject most commented by him when talking of humanity). For the man who
thinks backwards is very frequently a woman –he does accost clearly
womanhood and makes a speech which will be useful for him to criticise the
mankind itself later-.Thinking backwards is not quite easy to define
abstractedly; and, perhaps, the simplest method is to take some object, as
plain as possible, and from it illustrate the two modes of thought: the right
mode in which all real results have been rooted; the wrong mode, which is
confusing all our current discussions, especially our discussions about the
relations of the sexes”. Before proceeding with the heart of this article,
I’d better link this assortment of definition to his work “The Equality of
Sexlessness” (already studied) and this proves the real interest of Chesterton
in dividing the two flanks of human race, making relevant the current polemic
round discrimination. It’s essential to point out here that his main ambition
in politics is declaring himself as a Pacifist and defending this
movement. Only this way it can be understood his hatred towards war, which is frequently related to politics by him, fact
that turns both of these terms into two of the most important matters between
the host of beliefs he confesses.From a forward outlook, the man is watched
and, inherently, criticised so: “Among the live creatures that crawl about
this star the queerest is the thing called Man”. To be more clear is nearly
impossible, in my opinion: Chesterton demonstrates with those words the
profound imbecility of men, whom he qualifies as “This plucked and plumeless
bird, comic and forlorn” and “is the butt of all the philosophies. He is
the only naked animal; and this quality, once, it is said, his glory, is now
his shame. He has to go outside himself for everything that he wants. He might
almost be considered as an absent-minded who had gone bathing and left his
clothes everywhere, so that he has hung his hat upon the beaver and his coat
upon the sheep (in order to be more realistic, the essayist chooses some
common animals for comparing them to men). The rabbit has white warmth for a
waistcoat, and the glow-worm has a lantern for a head. But man has no heat in
his hide, and the light in his body is darkness; and he must look for light and
warmth in the wild, cold universe in which he is cast”. And soon he starts
to reflect on a mystical way, opposing to the scepticism and science of those
attacked before: “This is equally true of his soul and of his body; he is
the only creature that has lost his heart as much as he has lost his hide. In a
spiritual sense, he has taken leave of his senses; and even in a literal sense,
he has been unable to keep his hair on. And just as this external need of his
hat lit in his dark brain the dreadful star called religion (another
metaphor for presenting an equal fundamental factor, the one which probably
leads the essay), so it has lit in his hand the only adequate symbol of it:
I mean the red flower called Fire”.
After giving an
example of what it’s gonna be disputed, we find the definition of ‘thinking
forwards’: “He who has thus gone back to the beginning, and seen everything
as quaint and new, will always see things in their right order, the one
depending on the other in degree of purpose and importance: the poker for the
fire and the fire for the man and the man for the glory of God. This is
thinking forwards”.
To think
backwards, by its own, is available for the essayist’s cleverness to return to
modern attempts: “Before we begin discussing our various new plans for the
people’s welfare, let us make a kind of agreement that we will argue in a
straightforward way, and not in a tail-foremost way. The typical modern
movements may be right; but let them be defended because they are right, not
because they are typical modern movements”. At least now we can say there’s
an advantage, though a bit rigorous, of this issue which he makes great play
with. As in “The Real Journalist”, he goes on with reality and addresses the
readers in a global manner in which he himself includes: “Let us ask
ourselves first what we really do want, not what recent legal decisions have
told us to want, or recent logical philosophies’ proved that we must want, or
recent social prophecies predicted that we shall some day want”. In
conclusion, he supports thinking backwards: “In all such bewilderment he is
wise who resists this temptation of trivial triumph or surrender, and happy (in
an echo of the Roman poet) who remembers the roots of things”.
Is perhaps the
lack of this power-will by some writers what induces Chesterton to compose “A
Defence of Penny Dreadfuls”? I’ve made this question because it seems so
when one reads this essay –scanned by George Allaires- and finds out youth
short novels are not miserable, but the centre of plenty of fantasies: “One
of the strangest examples of the degree to which ordinary life is undervalued
is the example of popular literature, the vast mass of which we contentedly
describe as vulgar. The boy’s novelette may be ignorant in a literary sense,
which is only like saying that modern novel is ignorant in the chemical sense,
or the economic sense, or the astronomical sense; but it is not vulgar,
intrinsically it is the actual centre of a million flaming imaginations. In
former centuries, the educated class ignored the ruck of vulgar literature.
They ignored, and therefore did not, properly speaking, despise it”.
This sort of
literature must exist, as long as it’s a kind of need: “There is no class of
vulgar publications about which there is, to my mind, more utterly ridiculous
exaggeration and misconception than the current boys’ literature of the lowest
stratum. This class of composition has presumably always existed, and must
exist. It has no more claim to be good literature than the daily conversation
of its readers to be fine oratory, or the lodging-houses and tenements they
inhabit to be sublime architecture. But good people must have conversation,
they must have houses, and they must have stories. The simple need for some
kind of ideal world in which fictitious persons play an unhampered part is
infinitely deeper and older than the rules of good art, and much more
important”. As well it’s important to separate literature from the cheating
world of fiction, which are commonly joined but they’re really chalk and
cheese, and then Chesterton justifies what he said previously: “Literature
and fiction are two entirely different things. Literature is a luxury; fiction
is a necessity”. But we might wonder why these penny dreadfuls are so
brief? Gilbert Keith replies: “A story can never be too long, for its
conclusion is merely to be deplored, like the last halfpenny or the last
pipelight”. This sort of literature is often regarded as attached to
crimes: “It is the custom, particularly among magistrates, to attribute half
the crimes of the Metropolis to cheap novelettes (...) The boys themselves,
when penitent, frequently accuse the novelettes with great bitterness, which is
only to be expected from young people possessed of no little native humour”.
And, consequently, Chesterton denies the assertion this type of writing is a crime: “(...) it is firmly fixed in the minds of most
people that gutter-boys, unlike everybody else in the community, find their
principal motives for conduct in printed books. Now it is quite clear that this
objection, the objection brought by magistrates, has nothing to do with
literary merit. Bad story writing is not a crime”. Therefore, he criticises
the magisterial theory which accuses the Penny Dreadfuls: “The objection
rests upon the theory that the tone of the mass of boys’ novelettes is criminal
and degraded, appealing to low cupidity and low cruelty. This is the
magisterial theory, and this is the rubbish. So far as I have seen them, in
connection with the dirtiest book-stalls in the poorest districts, the facts
are simply these: the whole bewildering mass of vulgar juvenile literature is
concerned with adventures, rambling, disconnected, and endless. It does not
express any passion of any sort, for there is no human character of any sort”.
And it’s just that we don’t consider properly the lower classes, according to
the author’s sayings: “In the case of our own class, we recognise that this
wild life is contemplated with pleasure by the young, not because it is like
their own life, but because it is different from it (...) we lose our bearings
entirely by speaking of the ‘lower classes’ when we mean humanity minus
ourselves. This trivial romantic literature is not especially plebeian: it is
simply human”. So, defending penny dreadfuls and criticising what lectors
have done respect of them, our dearest Chesterton declares: “(...) this is
what we have done with this lumberland of foolish writing: we have probed, as
if it were some monstrous new disease, what is, in fact, nothing but the
foolish and valiant heart of man. Ordinary men will always be sentimentalists:
for a sentimentalist is simply a man who has feelings and does not trouble to
invent a new way of expressing them. These common and current publications have
nothing essentially evil about them. They express the sanguine and heroic
truisms, it is not built at all”.
He attacks, on
the other hand, modern literature -regarded as a sort of art in the society, what reflects the crucial
consideration the own Chesterton devotes to the action of writing itself-;
particularly, he draws a satire from the literature respecting to highbrow
people: “It is the modern literature of the educated, not of the uneducated,
which is avowedly and aggressively criminal. Books recommending profligacy and
pessimism, at which the high-souled errand-boy would shudder, lie upon all our
drawing-room tables”. He claims, in addition, that these penny dreadfuls
are not criminal, but we are the real criminals: “These things are our
luxuries. And with a hypocrisy so ludicrous as to be almost unparalleled in
history, we rate the gutter-boys for their immorality at the very time that we
are discussing (with equivocal German professors) whether morality (a usual
matter on him: let’s bring to mind “Negative and Positive Morality”, among
other instances) is valid at all. At the very instant that we curse the
Penny Dreadful for encouraging thefts upon property, we canvass the proposition
that all property is theft. At the very instant that we accuse it (quite
unjustly) of lubricity and indecency, we are cheerfully reading philosophies
which glory in lubricity and indecency. At the very instant that we charge it
with encouraging the young to destroy life, we are placidly discussing whether
life is worth preserving. But it is we who are morbid exceptions; it is we who
are the criminal class. This should be our great comfort (remarking here
the evident irony)”. And, to finish with that, he reassumes the critic
to educated people: “There are a large number of cultivated persons who
doubt these maxims of daily life, just as there are a large number of
cultivated persons who believe they are the Prince of Wales; and I am told that
both classes of people are entertaining conversationalists. But the average man
or boy writes daily in these great gaudy diaries of his soul, which we call
Penny Dreadfuls, a plainer and better gospel than any of those iridescent
ethical paradoxes that the fashionable change as often as their bonnets”. This
type of writing is obviously different from some other sorts of literature,
such as the aforementioned short novels (novelettes) or the Detective Stories, which he also named in any
occasion; precisely due to its singularity, Chesterton fixes his eyes on Penny
Dreadfuls, although it has already been proved why he truly defend them.
Finally, once
again talking of morality, he says popular romance is moral: “So long as the
coarse and thin texture of mere current popular romance is not touched by a
paltry culture, it will never be vitally immoral. It is always on the side of
life. The poor the slaves who really stoop under the burden of life have often
been mad, scatter-brained, and cruel, but never hopeless. That is a class
privilege, like cigars. Their drivelling literature will always be a ‘blood and
thunder’ literature, as simple as the thunder of heaven and the blood of men”;
as it finishes, he leaves a determinate savour of religion (‘heaven’) and
humanity (‘blood of men’) is left...
The remark made
by Chesterton when he said “(...) young people possessed of no little native
humour”, could be taken as a hint to mention his e-text “Cockneys and
their Jokes”, in progress, from an edition by John Lane Company -New York,
1909-, excerpted from “All The Things Considered”. As a whole, we can sum up in
advance it’s a text on the nature of humour. At first hand, it contains an
introduction to start with the subject and the first assertions, which are
fundamental and reveal us how the author is. There, “A writer in the
Yorkshire Evening Post is very angry indeed with my performances in this
column. His precise terms of reproach are: ‘Mr G.K. Chesterton is not a
humorist, not even a Cockney humorist’. I do not mind his saying I am not a
humorist –in which (to tell the truth) I think he is quite right. But I do
resent his saying that I am not a Cockney”. That proves the writer’s
patriotism and pride of being an inhabitant from London. “So I do not
urge that I am a humorist; but I do insist that I am a Cockney”.
“It is surely
sufficiently obvious that all the best humour that exists in our language is
Cockney humour (...) Even in our time, it may be noted that the most vital and
genuine humour is still written about London (...) I concede that I am not a
Cockney humorist”.
Gilbert speaks
of his City, London, and people from there: “London is the largest of the
bloated modern cities (this is clearly contrary to his personal beliefs, as
he hates modern world, but the fact of having been born there makes him worship
the place itself); London is the smokiest; London is the dirtiest; London
is, if you will, the most sombre; London is, if you will, the most miserable. So
far, we realise the description about the town is not optimistic or hopeful at
all, but this will change immediately, as soon ever as he determines: “But
London is certainly the most amusing and the most amused. You may prove that we
have the most tragedy; the fact remains that we have the most comedy, that we
have the most farce. We have, at the very worst, a splendid hypocrisy of
humour. We conceal our sorrow behind a screaming derision. You speak of people
who laugh through their tears; it is our boast that we only weep through our
laughter. There remains always this great boast, perhaps the greatest boast
that is possible to human nature. I mean the greatest that the most unhappy
part of our population is also the most hilarious part”. Like that contrast
we pointed between the tedious towards modernity and the boast of an English
patriot before, is reflected here with the help of matching opposites such as
laughter and tears, unhappiness and joy or tragedy and comedy, among others...
Partly inside
these comparisons, we come across the relationship with the poor and the rich
and the division of both categories: “The poor can forget that social
problem which we (the moderately rich) ought never to forget” » especial
stress this affirmation has: Chesterton includes himself inside the ‘moderately
Rich’ people; if it’s remarkable, it’s due to the following statement, which
happens to contradict the one mentioned: “Blessed are the poor –he takes
Christ’s own words-; for they alone have not the poor always with them. The
honest poor can sometimes forget poverty. The honest rich can never forget it”;
G.K. is plunging into philosophical or, “if you will”, moral matters.
Let’s turn back to “The Miser and His Friends” in case it’s necessary to clear
up the context, anyway. Forwardly, the essayist takes up the task of talking
about funny stories and adds precision to the explaining why they are made and
what for: “I believe firmly in the value of all vulgar notions, especially
of vulgar jokes. When once you have got hold of a vulgar joke, you may be
certain that you have got hold of a subtle idea. The men who made the joke saw
something deep which they could not express except by something silly and
emphatic. They saw something delicate which they could only express by
something indelicate” » a new contrasting, this time ‘delicate-indelicate’:
that shows the satire of criticising ordinary stuff. According to Mr Max
Beerbohm, there are 3 kinds of jokes: “I remember that Mr Max Beerbohm (who
has every merit except democracy) attempted to analyse the jokes at which the
mob laughs. He divided them into three sections: jokes about bodily
humiliation, jokes about things alien, such as foreigners, and jokes about bad
cheese”.
What really
impacted me was the presumable safety he shows when keeping: “In order to
understand vulgar humour it is not enough to be humorous. One must also be vulgar,
as I am”.Afterwards, he passes on to summarise the distinction of three
sections, according to Mr Beerbohm’s classification of jokes: “And in the
first case (...) If you really ask yourself why we laugh at a man sitting down
suddenly in the street, you will discover that the reason is not only
recondite, but ultimately religious” » we find the catholic sentiment even
related to humour. “(...) Quite equally subtle and spiritual is the idea at
the back of laughing at foreigners”; maybe we denote in that conclusion the
irritation he suffers every time he hears somebody making fun of one who does
not belong to the same country, and therefore we must highlight the subject of
patriotism again, at the time being the most essential point in this article. “(...)
Mr Max Beerbohm, I remember, professed to understand the first two forms of
popular wit, but said that the third quite stumped him. He could not see why
there should be anything funny about bad cheese” » once more, he resorts to
name the cheese as an element for proving what he supports. “(...) Bad
cheese symbolises the startling prodigy of matter taking on vitality. It
symbolises the origin of life itself. And it is only about such solemn matters
as the origin of life that the democracy condescends to joke”. He gathers
both, life and politics, and puts them aside the ‘bad cheese’, forming this way
a group in which every member is outstanding in the atmosphere of his thinking.
Otherwise, he could not be able to prove it, as it does now: “The vulgar
joke is, generally in the oddest way, the truth and yet not the fact (...) The
joke stands for an ultimate truth, and that is a subtle truth. It is not very
easy to state correctly”.
“But the vulgar
comic papers are so subtle and true that they are even prophetic”. Why all this?, e.g., how
can our writer demonstrate what he has said previously? “If you really want
to know what is going to happen to the future of our democracy, do not read the
modern sociological prophecies, do not read even Mr Wells’s Utopias for this
purpose, though you should certainly read them if you are found of good honesty
and good English » he makes a fool of Mr Wells and alludes to politics once
more because he’s drawing a speech of the democracy. “If you want to know
what will happen, study the pages of Snaps or Patchy Bits as if they were the
dark tablets graven with the oracles of gods. For, mean and gross as they are,
in all seriousness, they contain what is entirely absent from all Utopias and
all the sociological conjectures of our time: they contain some hint of the
actual habits and manifest desires of the English people”.
And lastly,
referring to literature itself: “If we are really to find out what the
democracy will ultimately do with itself, we shall surely find it, not in the
literature which studies the people, but in the literature which the people
studies”.
The conclusion
he extracts from this composition is the next: an example of when the common or
Cockney people were a much better prophecy that the careful observations of the
most highbrow observer; “The popular papers always persisted in representing
the New Woman or the Suffragette –he makes reference to this political
party anew, such as he did in “The Suffragist”- as an ugly woman, fat, in
spectacles, with bulging clothes, and generally falling off a bicycle”. And
he backs this specific sort of female insistently: “As a matter of plain
external fact, there was not a word of truth in this. The leaders of the
movement of female emancipation are not at all ugly; most of them are
extraordinarily good-looking. Nor are they different to art or decorative
costume; many of them are alarmingly attached to these things. Yet the popular
instinct was right. For the popular instinct was that in this movement, rightly
or wrongly, there was an element of indifference to female dignity, of a quite
new willingness of women to be grotesque. These women did truly despise the
pontifical quality of woman. And in our streets and around our Parliament we
have seen the stately woman of art and culture turn into the comic woman of
Comic Bits. And whether we think the exhibition justifiable or not, the
prophecy of the comic papers is justified: the healthy and vulgar masses were
conscious of a hidden enemy to their traditions who has now come out into the
daylight, that scriptures might be fulfilled. For the two things that a
healthy person hates most between heaven and hell are a woman who is not
dignified and a man who is”.
And, precisely
talking of femaleness, Gilbert Keith Chesterton also remembered his deceased
wife and incidentally wanted to commemorate his past and, in passing too,
introduce the subject of death. It was written in the last years of the
nineteenth century and consists of a monologue of him towards his sweetheart.
The first contact to her prays this way: “You want to talk to me about
death: my views about death are bright, brisk and entertaining”.
As follows, he wanders throughout his mind and may takes out the most
pessimistic perspective. “When Azrael takes a soul, it may be to other and
brighter worlds: like those whither you and I go together. The
transformation called Death (this is obviously an allegory of this
station in life) may be something as beautiful and dazzling as the
transformation called Love”. In fact, he tyrannises the act of
loving someone, as long as he compares it to Death, but recognises the beauty
of the action of being in love. “It may make the dead man ‘happy’, just as
your mother knows that you are happy. But none the less it is a
transformation, and sad sometimes for those left behind”. Next,
we reach the point of a relative’s affection –concretely her wife’s mother-,
and then we come across the issue of Family:“A mother whose child is
dying can hardly believe that in the inscrutable Unknown there is anyone who
can look to it as well as she. And if a mother cannot trust her child easily
to God Almighty, shall I be so mean as to be angry because she cannot trust it
easily to me?” » he takes as an instance the maternal affection to
compare to his love... “I tell you I have stood before your mother and felt
like a thief”. Chesterton addresses his wife confessing he does not believe
in spiritual or carnal death: “I know you are not going to part: neither
physically, mentally, morally nor spiritually. But she (her
mother) sees a new element in your life, wholly from outside –is it not
natural, given her temperament, that you should find her perturbed? Oh,
dearest, dearest Frances, let us always be very gentle to older people (he
claims for imposing respect towards the elderly lot and now he stands for their
defence). Indeed, darling, it is not they who are the tyrants, but we.
They may interrupt our building in the scaffolding stages: we turn their house
upside down when it is their final home and rest. Your mother would certainly
have worried if you had been engaged to the Archangel Michael (who, indeed, is
bearing his disappointment very well): how much more when you are engaged to an
aimless, tactless, reckless, unbrushed, strange-hatted, opinionated scarecrow
who has suddenly walked into the vacant place”. » as it can be appreciated,
he names Archangel Michael, what supposes to remind us of religion.
Chesterton agrees that his
wife’s mother is right: a mother always is concerned about her descendants’
marriages, so this one would not be an exception...“I could have
prophesied her unrest: wait and will calm down all right, dear. God comfort
her: I dare not...”. » and this is the way the letter ends.
And, at end, let’s evoke his writing
called “The Twelve Men” (from an essay in “Tremendous Trifles”, in
1909). Here we cross along a passage in which the author meddles with
jurisdiction attached to the courts. And, if I go over it, that is to throw
into relief the capacity this essayist has to sum up all his general ideas or
beliefs in a sole composition.
In fact, he remarks that, when being in a
court or, more concretely, in a jury box, “we settle down with a rollicking
ease into our seats (for we are a bold, devil-may-care race (...)), and an oath
is administered to us in a totally inaudible manner by an individual
resembling an army surgeon in his second childhood” » he may want to stick
out here the seriousness of a trial. Gilbert studies a determined case in a
court –which presumably chanced to bewilder him-: “(...) we pass on to a
woman who neglected her children, and who looks as if somebody or something had
neglected her. And I am one of those who fancy that something had. All the time
that the eye took in these light appearances and the brain passed these light
criticisms, there was in this heart a barbaric pity and fear which men have
never been able to utter from the beginning, but which is the power behind half
the poems of the world” » obviously, he backs women again and separate them
from maleness, who is not supposed to contain this tenderness. “The mood
cannot even inadequately be suggested –this proves the troubles existing
for explaining the sensation he felt before this event- except faintly by
this statement that tragedy is the highest expression of the infinite value
of human life”. Full of skill, Chesterton expresses, so, the
sensibility of mankind and ‘the infinite value’ it possesses. What it’s a pity
is that this feeling comes up just because of a tragic happening...
The same writer confesses sincerely: “Never
had I stood so close to pain; and never so far away from pessimism (an
interesting and extraordinary thing if we take into account tragedy also brings
uneasiness and often decay with it).
He regrets to have talked about those
sensations but, immediately, he justifies he did so in order to expose the
nucleus of this composition, that is, the existence of paradoxes, which drives
us towards the foundation of all religion and, particularly, the Christianity. “Ordinarily,
I should not have spoken of these dark emotions at all, for speech about them
is too difficult, but I mention them now for a specific and particular reason
to the statement of which I will proceed at once. I speak of these feelings
because, out of the furnace of them, there came a curious realisation of a
political or social truth. I saw with a queer and indescribable kind of
clearness what a jury really is, and why we must never let it go. The trend
of our epoch up to this time has been consistently towards socialism and
professionalism”. According to the last sentence –in bold letter-, we
are put into the matter of the past and politics too. “The principle has
been applied to law and politics by innumerable modern writers. Many Fabians –where
we can include Mr George Bernard Shaw, whom Chesterton devotes a notable
hostility- have insisted that a greater part of our political work should be
performed by experts. Many legalists have declared that the untrained jury
should be altogether supplanted by the trained Judge. Now, if this world of
ours were really what is called reasonable, I do not know that there would be
any fault to find with this. But the true result of all experience and the true
foundation of all religion is this. That the four or five things that it is
most practically essential that a man should know, are all of them what people
call paradoxes. That is to say, that though we all find them in
life to be mere plain truths, yet we cannot easily state them in words without
being guilty of seeming verbal contradictions. One of them, for instance, is
the unimpeachable platitude that the man who finds most pleasure for himself is
often the man who least bunts for it. Another is a paradox of courage; the fact
that the way to avoid death is not to have too much aversion to it”.
Perhaps the last assertion reaffirms what he said previously, in the letter to
Frances; he has never shown a feeling of terror in respect to demise.
At the moment, Gilbert Keith gets ready
to set out the fundamental sense of all the paradoxes and, therefore, the most
crucial of them: “Now, one of these four or five paradoxes which should be
taught to every infant prattling at his mother’s knee is the following: That
the more a man looks at a thing, the less he can see it, and the more a man
learns a thing, the
less he knows it. The Fabian argument of the expert, that the man who is trained should be
the man who is trusted, would be absolutely unanswerable if it were really true
that a man who studied a thing and practised it every day went on seeing more
and more of its significance. But he does not. He goes on seeing less and less
of its significance. In the same way, alas!, we all go on every day, unless
we are continually goading ourselves into gratitude and humility, seeing less
and less of the significance of the sky or the stones”. Once again, we are taught how stupid men are, as it has been commented
in “The Sectarian of Society” and “The Miser and His Friends”.
And, before closing this narration, this
English essayist goes into hiding to the religion: “(...) the instinct of
Christian civilisation has most wisely declared that into their judgements
there shall upon every occasion be infused fresh blood and fresh thoughts from
the streets”.
Then, speaking a bit of him time and society, he says: “Our civilisation has decided, and very justly decided (he
agrees them and boasts of being opposed to experts and Fabianism), that
determining the guilt or innocence of men is a thing too important to be
trusted to trained men. It wishes for light upon that awful matter, it asks men
who know no more law than I know, but who can feel the things that I felt in
the jury box” » as it should be, and this is what he has been claiming all
along the article, human personal feelings are the first and they prevail over
the law itself.
And finally, to surmount the present
affair, there’s a last reference to Christendom: “(...) when it wishes
anything done which is really serious, it collects twelve of the ordinary men
standing round. The same thing was done, if I remember right, by the Founder of
Christianity”.
Note: All these texts have been
selected from:"G.K. Chesterton Library".