GENDER TROUBLE
Judith Butler
Bricolage is perhaps the best term to use to think about what Judith Butler does
to and with Freud's psychoanalysis. She uses bits and pieces of Freud in order
to think about gender in a postmodern form, to problematize gender as category
of essence. She wants to question the idea that a person IS male or female,
masculine or feminine, which are the fundamental ideas Freud started with.
Butler wants to show that gender is not just a social construct, but rather a
kind of performance, a show we put on, a set of signs we wear, as costume or
disguise--hence as far from essence as can be.
She starts by asking questions about the category "woman:" who does it include,
and how do we know who it includes? And who decides what's in this category
anyway? We've already gone over this: in phallogocentric western discourse,
"woman" is always the other of "man", hence excluded from culture or the
Symbolic. In feminist theory, "woman" is universal category, which thus excludes
ideas of differences among women (differences of race, class, or sexuality, for
example). Both types of theory--psychoanalytic and feminist--rely on a notion of
"woman" as referring to an essence, a fact, a biological given, hence a
universal.
Given the pomo emphasis on discarding universals, "grand narratives,"
comprehensive categories, Butler says we need to think about "woman" as multiple
and discontinuous, not as a category with "ontological integrity." She turns to
psychoanalytic theory to do so. She gives an overview of Freud and Lacan (pp.
326-327) as setting up "woman" as eternal abstract universal category, and
implicates Irigaray in doing same thing.
Then she points to the poststructuralist theoretical feminists who destabilize
the concept of the subject as masculine/male by saying that the female isn't a
subject, isn't fully in the Symbolic, that "woman" is on the margins, in the
body, and is thus more free to play than man. But, if "woman" is not a subject,
can she have agency? And if there is no normative or unitary concept of "woman,"
can we have feminism as movement/theory? If there's no single "woman," then
there can be no single feminism.
Thus the problem is to think about woman as fragmentations, and about feminism
without a single unitary concept of woman.
Butler then looks at psychoanalysis as a "grand narrative," about how "woman" as
a unitary category is formed. Psychoanalysis is a story about origins and ends,
which includes some aspects, and excludes others, as Butler notes on p. 329. The
story starts with a utopian nondifferentiation of the sexes, which is ended by
enforced separation and the creation of difference. This narrative "gives a
false sense of legitimacy and universality to a culturally specific and, in some
cases, culturally oppressive version of gender identity."
In a way, Butler is asking the question about what happens in a psychoanalytic
paradigm if you don't have a mom and dad and no one else; if you're raised by
single parent, or two parents of the same sex, or by a grandmother, etc. She
looks at how the Freudian "grand narrative" privileges a certain story, certain
pattern of identifications, that supposedly produce a coherent unified gendered
self (man, woman, masculine, feminine), and says no, that's not how it really
works--you could have variations, fragmented identities, discontinuous or
provisional understandings of our gender identities based on wider variety of
identifications, beyond just mother/father/child.
Freud sets up a system where certain identifications are primary in forming a
(gendered) self, and others are secondary; the primary identifications have more
power to shape a self than the secondary ones, and are subordinated/subsumed
within the primary ones. Hence relations with the mother are primary (for both
sexes), while relations with siblings, eg., are secondary, not as important in
the narrative of how the gendered self is formed. The primary/secondary
identifications are temporal: the primary ones happen first, the secondary are
added on. Without that temporal placement (first this happens, then this
happens), you couldn't tell which identifications were more important than
others--which were substance and which were attributes. If we could redesign the
Oedipal narrative so it wasn't linear/temporal, we'd have all the
identifications going on at once, or without ranking--so that all would be
equally important, all would be attributes without one being substance (or all
would be copies without one being original).
Butler wants to understand gendered subjectivity "as a history of
identifications, parts of which can be brought into play in given contexts and
which, precisely because they encode the contingencies of personal history, do
not always point back to an internal coherence of any kind" (331).
She then presents the idea that the concept of the unconscious makes any idea of
coherence or unity suspect--whether we're talking about a slip of the tongue, or
any narrative/story--including the "grand narrative" of psychoanalysis. Freud's
story works hard to be unitary and coherent, to tell a connected story about how
gender is formed. It does so by repressing certain elements, excluding them from
the story. One of the ways it achieves this is to repress or exclude ideas of
simultaneity and multiplicity in gender and sexual identity. According to Freud,
you either identify with a sex OR you desire it; only those two relations are
possible. Thus it's not possible to desire the sex you identify with--if you are
a man desiring another man, for instance, Freud would say that's because you
REALLY identify with women.
Butler looks at how Freud tells the story of how fantasy identifications
(identifications that happen in the unconscious) shape our identity (who we
are). When we identify with someone else, we create an internal image of that
person, or, more precisely, who we want that person to be, and then we identify
with that internalized and idealized image. Our own identity, then, isn't
modeled on actual others but on our image of their image, on what we want the
other to be, rather than what the other really is.
Gender, then, as the identification with one sex, or one object (like the
mother) is a fantasy, a set of internalized images, and not a set of properties
governed by the body and its organ configuration. Rather, gender is a set of
signs internalized, psychically imposed on the body and on one's psychic sense
of identity. Gender, Butler concludes, is thus not a primary category, but an
attribute, a set of secondary narrative effects.
Gender is thus a fantasy enacted by "corporeal styles that constitute bodily
significations." In other words, gender is an act, a performance, a set of
manipulated codes, costumes, rather than a core aspect of essential identity.
Butler's main metaphor for this is "drag," i.e. dressing like a person of the
"opposite sex." All gender is a form of "drag," according to Butler; there is no
"real" core gender to refer to.