READER'S GUIDE TO
FOUCAULT'S "WHAT IS AN AUTHOR"?
The title
Even with his title,
Foucault is being provocative, taking a given and turning it into a problem.
His question ("What is an Author?") might even seem pointless at
first, so accustomed have we all become to thinking about authors and
authorship.
Section 1: 101-5
In the first few
paragraphs, Foucault responds to some of our most basic assumptions about
authorship. In the first paragraph, for example, Foucault reminds us that
although we regard the concept of authorship as "solid and
fundamental," that concept hasn't always existed. It "came into
being," Foucault explains, at a particular moment in history, and it may
pass out of being at some future moment.
In addition to touching on
our tendency to view the concept of authorship as "solid," Foucault
also seems to take up our habit of thinking about authors as individuals,
heroic figures who somehow transcend or step outside history. Why, he wonders,
are we so strongly inclined to view authors in that way? Why are we often so
resistant to the notion that authors are products of their times? (As I make
these points, incidentally, I'm not by any means trying to imply that you
should be picking up on them as you read Foucault. He is moving very quickly
here, leaving much unsaid.)
On pages 103-5, Foucault
does some jousting. First, he mixes it up with Roland Barthes, a very famous
literary critic, who had recently proclaimed the "death of the
author." According to Foucault, Barthes had urged other critics to realize
that they could "do without [the author] and study the work itself"
(104). This urging, Foucault implies, sounds a lot more radical than it really
is. (If you'd like to see for yourself, there's a copy of "Death of the
Author" on reserve.)
Next, on 104-5, Foucault
turns his attention to Derrida-- without ever mentioning his rival by name.
Foucault claims that although Derrida (like Barthes) presents his views as
radical, they are in truth quite conventional. Indeed, Foucault suggests,
Derrida never really gets rid of the author, but instead merely reassigns the
author's powers and privileges to "writing" or to "language itself."
Now, why does he bother to
do all this? Well, partly because he enjoys a fight, and partly because he
doesn't want his readers to assume that authorship is a "dead issue,"
a problem that's already been solved by Barthes and Derrida. His aim here is to
show that, despite all of their bombast, neither Barthes nor Derrida has broken
away from the question of the author--much less solved it.
Section 2: 105-8
In this section, Foucault
asks us to think about the ways in which an author's name "functions"
in our society. After raising questions about the functions of proper names, he
goes on to say that the names of authors often serve a
"classifactory" function.
To get a sense of what he
means, just think about how the average bookstore is laid out. If you were to
go to the fiction section at Conkey's, looking for a copy of Oliver Twist,
chances are that you wouldn't search for books about workhouses, or books
written in 1837, or books that are 489 pages long. You'd search for books
written by Charles Dickens. It probably wouldn't even occur to you to make your
search in any other way.
Now, Foucault asks, why do
you--why do most of us--assume that it's "natural" for Conkey's to
classify books according to the names of their authors? While you're mulling
over that one, think about this: What would happen to Oliver Twist if
scholars were to discover that it hadn't been written by Charles Dickens?
Wouldn't most bookstores, and wouldn't most of us, feel that the novel would
have to be reclassified in light of that discovery? Why should we feel that
way? After all, the words of the novel wouldn't have changed, would they?
Foucault closes this
section by introducing his concept of the "author function." Note
that the "author function" is not a person and is not to be confused
with either the "author" or the "writer." The "author
function" is more like a set of beliefs or assumptions governing the
production, circulation, classification and consumption of texts. (Put another
way, it's the thing that makes us want to know about the author of a poem--and
never think of asking about the author of a commercial or a contract.)
Section 3: 108-13
Here, Foucault identifies
and describes four characteristics of the "author function." The characteristics
are, briefly:
1. The "author function" is linked to
the legal system and arises as a result of the need to punish those responsible
for transgressive statements.
2.
The "author function" does not affect all texts in the same way. For
example, it doesn't seem to affect scientific texts as much as it affects
literary texts. If a chemistry teacher is talking about the periodic table, you
probably wouldn't stop her and say, "Wait a minute--who's the author of
this table?" If I'm talking about a poem, however, you might very well
stop me and ask me about its author.
3.
The "author function" is more complex than it seems to be. This is
one of the most difficult points in the essay, and in thinking about it, you
might want to consider what Foucault says about the editorial problem of
attribution-- the problem of deciding whether or not a given text should be
attributed to a particular author.
This problem may seem rather trivial, since
most of the literary texts that we study have already been reliably attributed
to an author. Imagine, however, a case in which a scholar discovered a
long-forgotten poem whose author was completely unknown. Imagine, furthermore,
that the scholar had a hunch that the author of the poem was William
Shakespeare. What would the scholar have to do, what rules would she have to
observe, what standards would she have to meet, in order to convince everyone
else that she was right?
A
few years ago, this imaginary situation became a reality, when a scholar named
Gary Taylor suddenly announced that he had rediscovered a long-long Shakespeare
poem. Many, many people viewed Taylor's announcement with skepticism, and in
arguing against Taylor, they did resort (without realizing it, of course) to
the "criteria of authenticity" proposed by St. Jerome and listed by
Foucault on page 111. They argued, for instance, that the poem wasn't good
enough to have been authored by Shakespeare--on the assumption, I gather, that
Shakespeare was somehow incapable of sinking below a certain level of literary
excellence. It may help to keep this sort of situation in mind, as you try to
make sense of this third characteristic of the "author function."
4.
The term "author" doesn't refer purely and simply to a real
individual. The "author" is much like the "narrator,"
Foucault suggests, in that he or she can be an "alter ego" for the
actual flesh-and-blood "writer."
If you're
unsure of what Foucault means by any of this, check out his own summary on page
113. And if you're unclear about a little point here or there, don't worry. The
main thing is that you understand his main goal for this section--which is to
describe four main characteristics of the "author function."
Section 4: 113-7
Here, Foucault takes off in
a different direction, and his aim now is to show that the "author
function" applies not just to individual works, but also to larger
discourses. This, then, is the famous section on "founders of
discursivity"--guys like Marx or Freud who produce their own texts, plus "the
possibilities or the rules for the formation of other texts." I don't
think that this issue is particularly difficult, so I won't belabor it.
I do want to comment,
however, on what Foucault has to say about science. According to Foucault,
scientists can't really be "founders of discursivity." In making that
statement, Foucault seems to be distinguishing scientific discourses (in which
there are, he suggests, a limited number of possible statements) from
discourses like that of psychoanalysis (in which the number of possible statements
is not and cannot be limited). I'm not sure that I understand everything he has
to say about this issue, but I do feel pretty sure of that much.
Section 5: 117-20
In this section, Foucault
wraps things up and points out a few reasons why he's bothered with this
particular subject in the first place. He raises the possibility of doing a
"historical analysis of discourse," and he notes that the
"author function" has operated differently in different places and at
different times.
His comments about the
"subject" are hard to decipher, and I'm not sure that they need to be
decoded in full. Just remember that he began this essay by questioning our
tendency to imagine "authors" as individuals isolated from the rest
of society. He's raising the same sort of question here--and also taking a
further step, suggesting that if we stop thinking of authors as isolated
individuals, we may also be able to stop thinking of other people and kinds of
people in that way. (Here, one might hear a faint echo of Marxism, which often
tends to see individual preferences and tastes as products of larger social
forces.)
Near the end of the essay,
Foucault argues that the author is not a source of infinite meaning, as we
often like to imagine, but rather part of a larger system of beliefs that serve
to limit and restrict meaning. In pondering this idea, think about how we might
appeal to ideas of "authorial intention" in order to limit what
someone might say about a text, or mark some interpretations and commentaries
as illegitimate.
At the very end, Foucault
returns to Barthes and agrees that the "author function" may soon
"disappear." He does not suggest, however, that the limiting and
restrictive "author function," we will have some kind of absolute freedom.
One set of restrictions and limits will give way to another set, Foucault
insists, since there must and will always be some "system of
constraint" working upon us.
© http://www.lawrence.edu/dept/english/courses/60A/handouts/author.html