Heidegger meant by "the end of philosophy" the
end of a philosophy rooted in metaphysics. He argued that the only real
philosophical questions have to do with "being" (ontology) and that "transcendental"
questions were meaningless. By the sixties, the notion of the "end of philosophy
" had developed into the notion that philosophy was nothing other than
the ideology of the western ethos. The liberal humanist tradition presented
a de facto situation (its own pre-eminence) as a de jure situation (its
truth). In other words, it presented its traditional privilege as a natural
superiority. Such a position is ideological.
Derrida argued that Heidegger had not escaped
transcendentalism, that his "Being" was as transcendental as any other
"Transcendental Signified." He also argued that even if the charge against
philosophy as ideology were true, the charge was levelled in the language
of philosophy, which can not be escaped. All that was really being asked
was that the dominant ideology (philosophy = the ideology of the western
ethos) be replaced by another broader or at least different ideology such
as Marxism (philosophy=discourse of the ruling class), Freudianism (philosophy
=sexual symptom), anti-Freudianism (philosophy =phallocratic ideology).
In the end, he argued, the order of reason is absolute, "since it is only
to itself that an appeal against it can be brought, only in itself that
a protest against it can be made; on its own terrain, it leaves us no other
recourse than to stratagem and strategy."
Derrida did not quarrel with Heidegger's position
that history, as perceived in the philosophic tradition was over; only
that Heidegger himself had not escaped it. Derrida raised the question
of what there was to say after philosophy was over (but ironically still
in place, because reason is absolute and can only be questioned in its
own terms). The strategy he chose was duplicity, the playing of a double
game. He would operate in the language of reason, since there was no other,
but try to lay traps for it by posing it problems it could not answer,
exposing the inherent contradictions in apparently reasonable positions.
He called this strategy deconstruction, after Heidegger's term destruktion.
For Heidegger, destruktion was essentially, the
history of the inquiry into history. Dasein , the individual's being in
the world, is often trapped by the everyday ordinariness of life into interpreting
itself in terms of the world it knows and the tradition it inherits. This
condition Heidegger calls fallenness, and the individuals who have fallen
into it das man (the they). Anyone who wishes to live authentically must
escape from the average everyday ordinariness of life and contemplate his/her
own death (non-being, or nothingness). This is done through the agency
of angst , a kind of generalized suffering caused by the fear of dying,
and the intellectual exercise of destruktion. Destruktion, then is a combination
of a negative analysis of "today," the average everyday world and a positive
analysis of history that tries to achieve authenticity through the rigorous
questioning of accepted authority. Often this means breaking a word into
its component parts in order to trace its history.
Derrida's deconstruction is a more limited but
even more rigorous form of interrogation. Since the "speaking subject,"
when he/she speaks, must speak the language of reason, there must exist
some silent region where the double agent deconstructor can sort out his
stratagem against the Logos, the rules of reason. In order for this to
be possible, two conditions must maintain:
1. In order for the double game of duplicity
to be played, the language of philosophy must already be full of duplicity
(both in its sense of doubleness and its sense of hypocrisy or lying.)
2. The strategist (speaking subject, deconstructor)
must resist the power of Logos (reason) by maintaining a indefensible position
of empiricism, erasing the distinction between truths of fact and truths
of reason. This will be accomplished through différance.
For Heidegger, difference was the result of temporality.
Since history and language precede the self and help construct the self,
the self can never step outside itself and see itself outside of history
and language. The self (in Heidegger's language dasein) can only conceive
an historically past self, different from the existential self experiencing
the world in the present. In that sense, the self (as subject) is always
different from the self (as object).
Derrida's concept la différance contains
two notions: difference and deference, a separation of identity and a separation
in time. Derrida came to his notion through an attempt to show the impossibility
of Husserl's promise of a "phenomenology of history" by deconstructing
the notion. He showed that a phenomenology of history would have to answer
the question "how is a truth possible for us?" But if a truth is to be
truth, it must be absolute, independent of any point of view(unless, of
course, we are God, in which case the question is meaningless). Phenomenology
seeks the origin of truth, and it locates this origin in an inaugural fact
which by definition can only occur once.
The phenomenologist argues that only the present
exists. The past is retained in the present through the present ruins of
a civilization that is absent. The future is mooted, or predicted, but
only in the present. But in order for the past to be retained in the present
and the future to beannounced in the present, the present must not only
be present. It must also be a present that is still to come (future) and
a present that is already past (past). At this point difference appears.
The present is not identical with itself.
This difference raises again the problem of the
inaugural fact Suppose we have the trace of some inaugural event, say the
stone foundations at L'Anse aux Meadows. Out of our present we may for
ourselves assume these to be Viking remains, though we cannot with certainty
know what meaning they had for their makers. We cannot make our meaning
coincide with their meaning, yet we know that when that past was a present,
it had all the properties of a present. That other must also be a same.
Again, this failure of the past to coincide with itself is a source of
différance.
If we are to develop a phenomenology of history
we must posit what Husserl called "a principle of principles." This principle
is that history is meaningful, and however confused or in need of mediation,
it can be transmitted from generation to generation. It is univocal, even
though it can never be articulated at any moment. Being and meaning can
never coincide except at infinity, so meaning is always deferred. The de
jure situation (what is right) and the de facto situation (what is fact)
can also never coincide. The reason for this is that there is an originary
difference between fact and right, being and meaning.
Another necessary but paradoxical concept is
the idea of originary delay. Derrida argues that a first is only a first
by consequence of a second that follows it. The first is only recognizable
as a first and not merely a singular by the arrival of the second. The
second is therefore the prerequisite of the first. It permits the first
to be first by its delayed arrival. The first, recognizable only after
the second, is in this respect a third. Origin, then is a kind of dress
rehearsal, what Derrida calls la répétition d'une première,
in terms of the theatre, a representation of the first public performance
which has not yet occurred. The original, in that sense, is always a copy.
In this way, Derrida deconstructs Husserl's principle of principles which
always relied on being able to distinguish the original from later copies.
If we apply the same analysis to signs and things
in the "real" world we come to the paradoxical situation that the sign
precedes the referent. The sign "dog," precedes the four-legged barking
creature because the creature is only recognizable as that after the sign
"dog" has been applied to it. Derrida has shown that, contrary to Husserl's
notion of a pure origin, consciousness never precedes language,, and we
cannot see language as a representation of a silently lived through experience.
This is the core of deconstructive thinking.
We can only understand the priority of the sign by an enquiry into writing.
Earlier, we looked at graphemes (the units of writing) as a second-order
sign system. Derrida sees the relationship between these signs as semiological.
The graphic sign stands in for the phonemic sign. It is therefore "the
sign of a sign," while the oral sign is the "sign of the thing." Writing
is then supplementary. (Even the oral sign is supplementary, since it exists
as supplement to the "real world." The graphic sign of writing is particularly
supplemental since it is a supplement to a supplement, a sign of a sign.)
In Off Grammatology Derrida argues that writing should not be subordinated
to speech, and this subordination is nothing more than an historical prejudice.
He argues further that to define a graphic sign is to define any sign.
Every sign is a signifier whose signified is another signifier. Think of
looking up signifiers in a dictionary. What you get is a list of other
signifiers. Meaning is always deferred.
The idea of the supplement raises some interesting
questions. We can think of the origin as a place where there is no originary,
only a supplement in the place of a deficient originary. It is deficient
for this reason. We can think of the supplement as a surplus, something
extra added to the whole and outside of it. But if the whole is really
the whole, then nothing can be added to it. If the supplement is something
and not nothing, then it must expose the defect of the whole, since something
that can accomodate the addition of a supplement must be lacking something
within itself. Derrida calls this "the logic of the supplement."
In the same way, the present is only present
on the condition that it allude to the absence from which it distinguishes
itself. Metaphysics, Derrida argues, is the act of erasing this distinguishing
mark, the trace of the absent. We may now define trace as the sign left
by the absent thing, after it has passed on the scene of its former presence.
Every present, in order to know itself as present, bears the trace of an
absent which defines it. It follows then that an originary present must
bear an originary trace, the present trace of a past which never took place,
an absolute past. In this way, Derrida believes, he achieves a position
beyond absolute knowledge.
Derrida distinguishes between a meditating on
presence, which he defines as philosophy, and the possibility of meditating
on non-presence. How can these two kinds of thinking, one of which takes
issue with the other co-exist? Derrida argues that philosophy is always
already there (not that it has always been.) Philosophy can only be a thinking
of presence, since experience is lived and tested in the present. The other
kind of thinking which is not philosophical cannot therefore appeal to
individual empirical experience. Instead it appeals to a general experience.
At the level of text, then, the appeal is to
writing in general. Every text is a double text. It is philosophical and
and understood by classical interpretation at one level of its reading.
But it also contains traces and contradictions, indications of the second
text which a classical reading can never uncover. No synthesis is possible.
The second text is not an opposite which can be reconciled. It is what
Derrida calls its counterpart, slightly phased. It requires a deconstructive
reading of the difference (what Derrida calls a double science or double
séance).
The meditation on non-presence is a meditation
on the self as other. Every metaphysical text is separated from itself
by what Derrida calls a "scarcely perceptible veil." A slight displacement
in the reading of the text
is sufficient to collapse one into the other,
to make comedy wisdom or vice versa. Derrida's duplicity splits the metaphysical
text in two, revealing its inherent contradictions. Derrida's analysis
insists on the undecidability of words, their unresolvable contradictions.
One of the most important concepts in Derrida's
analysis is the idea of "sous rature," (under erasure.) Heidegger often
crossed out the word Being (Being) and let both the word and its erasure
stand. He felt the Being was prior to and beyond signification or meaning,
and hence to signify it was inadequate, though there existed no alternative.
Derrida extends this practise to all signs. Since any signifier has as
its signified another signifier, it always defers meaning and it always
carries traces of other meanings. It must therefore be studied as defective,
incomplete, under erasure.
A few (over-simplified) definitions:
Grammatology: The science of writing. Derrida proposes to move beyond traditional models of writing that describe its history and evolution to develop a theory of writing, to apply that theory and to move in the direction of a new writing. The difficult in doing so is the result of the relationship between writing and metaphysics.
The metaphysics of presence. The assumption that the physical presence of a speaker authenticates his speech. Speaking would then precede writing (the sign of a sign), since the writer is not present at the reading of his text to authenticate it. Spoken language is assumed to be directly related to thought, writing a supplement to spoken language, standing in for it. This is the result of phonocentrism the valorization of speech over writing.
Logocentrism: "In the beginning was the word." Logocentrism is the belief that knowledge is rooted in a primeval language(now lost) given by God to humans. God (or some other transcendental signifier: the Idea, the Great Spirit, the Self, etc;) acts a foundation for all our thought, language and action. He is the truth whose manifestation is the world. He is the foundation for the binaries by which we think: God/Man, spiritual/physical, man/woman, good/evil. The first term of the binary is valorized, and a chain of binaries constitutes a hierarchy.
Binary Oppositions: The hierarchical relation of elements that results from logocentrism. Derrida is interested more in the margins, the supplements, than in the centre.
The supplement: Derrida takes this term from Rousseau, who saw a supplement as "an inessential extra added to something complete in itself." Derrida argues that what is complete in itself cannot be added to, and so a supplement can only occur where there is an originary lack. In any binary set of terms, the second can be argued to exist in order to fill in an originary lack in the first. This relationship, in which one term secretly resides in another, Derrida calls invagination.
Originary lack: Some absence in a thing that permits it to be supplemented.
Metonymic chain: Derrida argues with Saussure's notion that signs are binary. (signifier, signified) The signified, he says, is always a signifier in another system. As a result, meaning cannot be in a sign, since it is always dispersed, deferred and delayed. (dictionary analogy). In terms of a text, then, all signifiers must be seen as defective. A signifier always contains traces of other signifiers.
Trace: The indications of an absence that define a presence. (The present is known as the present only through the evidence of a past that once was a present.) The traces of other signifiers in any signifier means that it must always be read under erasure.(sur rasure).
Erasure: The decision to read a signifier or a text as if its meaning were clear, with the understanding that this is only a strategy.
Difference (Différance) A pun on difference
and deference. Any signifier (or chain of signification, ie. text) must
infinitely defer its meaning because of the nature of the sign (the signified
is composed of signifiers). At the same time, meaning must be kept under
erasure because any text is always out of phase with itself, doubled, in
an argument with itself that can be glimpsed through the aporias it generates.
Deconstruction: an attempt to dismantle the binary
oppositions which govern a text by focussing on the aporias or impasses
of meaning. A deconstructive reading will identify the logocentric assumptions
of a text and the binaries and hierarchies it contains. It will demonstrate
how a logocentric text always undercuts its own assumptions, its own system
of logic. It will do this largely through an examination of the traces,
supplements, and invaginations in the text.
ENGL 4F70, Contemporary Literary Theory, Brock
University
Deconstruction: Some Assumptions
Copyright 1996 by John Lye. This text may be freely
used, with attribution, for non-profit purposes.