Works
System
of Logic
(1843)
Principles of Political Economy (1848)
On
Liberty
(1859)
Utilitarianism
(1861)
Representative
Government
(1861)
The
Subjection of Women (1861, published in 1869)
Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy (1865)
Speech
In Favor of Capital Punishment
Utilitarianism
Mill's
Utilitarianism
(1861) is an extended explanation of utilitarian moral theory. In an effort
to respond to criticisms of the doctrine, Mill not only argued in favor
of the basic principles of Jeremy
Bentham but also offered several significant improvements to its structure,
meaning, and application. Although the progress of moral philosophy has
been limited by its endless disputes over the reality and nature of the
highest good, Mill assumed from the outset, everyone can agree that the
consequences of human actions contribute importantly to their moral value.
(Utilitarianism 1)
"
. . . actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness,
wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is
intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the
privation of pleasure."
(Utilitarianism 2)
But
he did not agree that all differences among pleasures can be quantified.
On Mill's view, some kinds of pleasure experienced by human beings also
differ from each other in qualitative ways, and only those who have experienced
pleasure of both sorts are competent judges of their relative quality.
This establishes the moral worth of promoting higher (largely intellectual)
pleasures among sentient beings even when their momentary intensity may
be less than that of alternative lower (largely bodily) pleasures. Even
so, Mill granted that the positive achievement of happiness is often difficult,
so that we are often justified morally in seeking primarily to reduce the
total amount of pain experienced by sentient beings affected by our actions.
Pain—or even the sacrifice of pleasure—is warranted on Mill's view only
when it results directly in the greater good of all.
Against
those who argue that the utilitarian theory unreasonably demands of individual
agents that they devote their primary energies to the cold-hearted and
interminable calculation of anticipated effects of their actions, Mill
offered a significant qualification. Precisely because we do not have the
time to calculate accurately in every instance, he supposed, we properly
allow our actions to be guided by moral rules most of the time. Partly
anticipating the later distinction between act
and rule utilitarianism, Mill pointed out that secondary moral principles
at the very least perform an important service by providing ample guidance
for every-day moral life. Finally, however, he emphasized that the value
of each particular action—especially in difficult or controversial cases—is
to be determined by reference to the principle of utility itself.
What
motivates people to do the right thing? Mill claimed universal agreement
on the role of moral sanctions in eliciting proper conduct from human agents.
(Utilitarianism 3) But unlike Bentham, Mill did not restrict himself
to the socially-imposed external sanctions of punishment and blame, which
make the consequences of improper action more obviously painful. On Mill's
view, human beings are also motivated by such internal sanctions as self-esteem,
guilt, and conscience. Because we all have social feelings on behalf of
others, the unselfish wish for the good of all is often enough to move
us to act morally. Even if others do not blame or punish me for doing wrong,
I am likely to blame myself, and that bad feeling is another of the consequent
pains that I reasonably consider when deciding what to do.
In
Chapter Four, Mill offers as "proof" of the principle of utility an argument
originally presented by his father, James
Mill. The best evidence of the desirability of happiness is that people
really do desire it; and since each individual human being desires her
own happiness, it must follow that all of us desire the happiness of everyone.
Thus, the Mills argued, the greatest pleasure of all is morally desirable.
(Utilitarianism 4) The argument doesn't hold up well at all in logical
terms, since each of its inferences is obviously fallacious, but Mill may
have been correct in supposing on psychological grounds that seeking pleasure
and avoiding pain are the touchstones by which most of us typically live.
Finally,
Mill argued that social applications of the principle of utility are fully
consistent with traditional concern for the promotion of justice. Justice
involves respect for the property, rights, and deserts of individual citizens,
along with fundamental presumptions in favor of good faith and impartiality.
All of these worthwhile components of justice are adequately preserved
by conscientious application of the principle of utility, Mill supposed,
since particular cases of each clearly result in the greatest happiness
of all affected parties. (Utilitarianism 5) Although a retributive
sentiment in favor of punishing wrong-doers may also be supposed to contribute
to the traditional concept of justice, Mill insisted that the appropriately
limited use of external sanctions on utilitarian grounds better accords
with a legitimate respect for the general welfare. Mill also pointed out
that the defence of individual human freedom is especially vital to living
justly, but that had been the subject of another book.
On
Liberty
John
Stuart Mill's On Liberty (1859) is the classic statement
and defence of the view that governmental encroachment upon the freedom
of individuals is almost never warranted. A genuinely civil society, he
maintained, must always guarantee the civil liberty of its citizens—their
protection against interference by an abusive authority. This is true even
when the government itself relies upon the democratic participation of
the people. (On Liberty 1) The tyranny of the majority is especially
dangerous to individual liberty, Mill supposed, because the most commonly
recommended remedy is to demand that the recalcitrant minority either persuade
the majority to change its views or learn to conform to socially accepted
norms.
Mill
had a different notion. The proper balance between individual liberty and
governmental authority, he proposed, can be stated as a simple principle:
"[T]he
only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member
of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others."
(On Liberty 1)
Although
society has a clear responsibility for protecting its citizens from each
other, it has no business interfering with the rest of what they do. In
particular,
anything that directly affects only the individual citizen must remain
absolutely free. On Mill's view, this entails in particular that the government
is never justified in trying to control, limit, or restrain: 1) private
thoughts and feelings, along with their public expression, 2) individual
tastes and pursuits as efforts to live happily, or 3) the association of
like-minded individuals with each other. (On Liberty 1) No society
is truly free unless its individual citizens are permitted to take care
of themselves.
Considering
first freedom of thought and discussion, Mill argued that because even
a majority opinion is fallible, society should always permit the expression
of minority views. There is a chance, after all, that the unconventional
opinion will turn out, in the long run, to be correct, in which case the
entire society would suffer if it were never allowed to come to light.
Sincere devotion to the truth requires open inquiry, not the purposeful
silencing of alternative views that might prove to be right. (On Liberty
2) Even if the unconventional opinion turns out to be incorrect, Mill argued,
there is still good reason to encourage its free expression. The truth
can only be enlivened and strengthened by exposure to criticism and debate
through which the majority view is shown not to be merely an inadequately
grounded superstition. (On Liberty 2) In the most common instance,
Mill supposed, there will actually turn out to be some measure of falsity
in the clearest truth and some element of truth in the most patent falsehood.
Thus, on every possible occasion, encouraging civil discussion of alternative
views genuinely benefits society as a whole.
Mill
supposed that behavior as well as thought often deserves protection against
social encroachment. Human action should arise freely from the character
of individual human beings, not from the despotic influence of public opinion,
custom, or expectation. No matter what patterns of behavior may constitute
the way we ought to be, he argued, each person must choose her or his own
path in life, even if it differs significantly from what other people would
recommend. (On Liberty 3) No less than in the realm of thought,
in the realm of behavior unconventionality and originality are often signs
of great personal genius, which should never be curtailed by social pressures.
In
summary, then, Mill emphasized that individual citizens are responsible
for themselves, their thoughts and feelings, and their own tastes and pursuits,
while society is properly concerned only with social interests. In particular,
the state is justified in limiting or controlling the conduct of individuals
only when doing so is the only way to prevent them from doing harm to others
by violating their rights. (On Liberty 4) Where the conduct in question
affects only the person who does it—even if it clearly results in harm
to that person—the state has no business in even trying to suppress the
mode of being that person has chosen. Thus, on Mill's view, legislation
that attempts to promote good conduct or to prevent people from harming
themselves is always wrong. The line he drew between private and social
concerns is a fairly clear one: society should not endeavor to limit my
drinking, but rightly prosecutes me for harming others while drunk.
In
the essay's final chapter, Mill carefully noted several apparent exceptions
to the general principle. (On Liberty 5) Governmental interference
is not necessary even in some of the instances where it might be justifiable.
Economic life involves social interest and may therefore be subject to
regulation, even though free trade is often more effective. Speech or action
by one individual that encourages someone else to commit self-harm is appropriately
restricted. Indirect action by the state designed to encourage or discourage
(without requiring or restraining) individual conduct is permissible; in
fact, doing so is simply good utilitarian legislation. According to Mill,
the state's legitimate interest in preventing harm to its citizens extends
even into the domain of family life, as in forbidding spousal abuse or
providing for the education of children.
Finally,
Mill noted that even if the involvement of the government in some specific
aspect of the lives of its citizens does not violate their individual liberty,
there may remain other good reasons for avoiding it. If the conduct to
be regulated can be performed better by individuals themselves, if it is
more desirable that it be done by them, or if regulation would add significantly
to the already-dangerous power of the social establishment, then the state
ought not to be allowed to interfere. (On Liberty 5) Mill's conclusion,
then, is strictly in favor of liberty: governmental action is legitimate
only when demonstrably necessary for the protection of other citizens from
direct harm caused by the conduct in question. On every other contingency,
the liberty of the individual should remain inviolate.
The
Subjection of Women
One
of Mill's last and finest literary efforts was written in support of a
political cause of which he had long been a leading champion. The Subjection
of Women (1869) offered both detailed argumentation and passionate
eloquence in bitter opposition to the social and legal inequalities commonly
imposed upon women by a patriarchal
culture. Mill granted the practical difficulty of arguing successfully
against an opinion that is widely-held and deeply-entrenched even though
it relies upon nothing better than a vaguely-expressed presumption of the
natural superiority of males. In fact, Mill pointed out, the domination
of men over women—like conquest or slavery in any other form—originated
in nothing more than the brute application of physical power. But this
reliance upon physical force as a means of obtaining and maintaining control
over other human beings has been abandoned in every other area of political
life.
"The
social subordination of women thus stands out an isolated fact in modern
social institutions; a solitary breach of what has become their fundamental
law . . . ." (Subjection
of Women 1)
Mill
argued that reliance upon physical strength and violence should not be
tolerated in this instance, either.
Although
it is often claimed that male domination over women is a purely natural
expression of biological necessity, Mill found little genuine evidence
for this. Any conventional social discrimination, made familiar by long
experience and social prevalence, will come to seem natural to those who
have never contemplated any alternative. The appearance of voluntary submission
by women is even more misleading, on Mill's view, since it could as easily
reflect enslavement of mind and feeling as genuine sentiment. Certainly
men, whose awareness of women's thinking is severly limited, are in no
position to speak confidently about what women really want:
"Many
a man thinks he perfectly understands women, because he has had amatory
relations with several, perhaps with many of them. If he is a good observer,
and his experience extends to quality as well as quantity, he may have
learnt something of one narrow department of their nature—an important
department, no doubt. But of all the rest of it, few persons are generally
more ignorant, because there are few from whom it is so carefully hidden."
(Subjection of Women 1)
If
society really wanted to discover what is truly natural in gender
relations, Mill argued, it should establish a free market for all of the
services women perform, ensuring a fair economic return for their contributions
to the general welfare. Only then would their practical choices be likely
to reflect their genuine interests.
In
the
patriarchal
culture, many women are trapped by social expectations in the traditional
forms of marriage, which had its origins as bondage or involuntary servitude.
Although Mill granted that some men are less despotic toward their wives
than the laws would permit, he supposed this a mixed blessing and noted
those who wish to do so find little difficulty in securing a slave-wife.
Mill saw no reason why either partner in a marriage should dominate the
other; he proposed that a family governed by consenual separation of functions
could, in principle become a profoundly serious example of free association.
"What
marriage may be in the case of two persons of cultivated faculties, identical
in opinions and purposes, between whom there exists that best kind of equality,
similarity of powers and reciprocal superiority in them—so that each can
enjoy the luxury of looking up to the other, and can have alternately the
pleasure of leading and of being led in the path of development—I will
not attempt to describe. To those who can conceive it, there is no need;
to those who cannot, it would appear the dream of an enthusiast. But I
maintain, with the profoundest conviction, that this, and this only, is
the ideal of marriage; and that all opinions, customs, and institutions
which favour any other notion of it, or turn the conceptions and aspirations
connected with it into any other direction, by whatever pretences they
may be coloured, are relics of primitive barbarism."
(Subjection of Women 4)
Although
few men can presently tolerate the prospect of living in intimate association
with a genuinely equal partner, Mill clearly believed it not only possible
but highly desirable to do so.
Thus,
the liberation of women from patriarchal
restrictions holds great promise for human life generally. The individual
property rights of women ought to be wholly independent of their marital
status, for example, and their right to participate in the political process
ought to be granted completely. (Efforts to secure suffrage for women had
been a major issue of Mill's own service in the British Parliament.) Not
only can women think as well as men, Mill argued, but their thought and
experience inclines them to be more flexible and practical in applied reasoning
and, perhaps, therefore morally superior to men. Certainly the provision
of social equality for women would serve the general welfare of society
by promoting justice, enhancing moral sensitivity, and securing liberty
for all.
©1999-2000 Garth Kemerling.
© Neus Vicens Morant, 2001.
Tornar a John Stuart
Mill